Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-mlc7c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T15:17:43.111Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Causality, Meaning and Purpose in Politics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 August 2009

Abstract

Political science is in a state of crisis today. The crisis is the result of the scientistic predicament. Man has become the victim of his own reason and knowledge. Scientific rationality and value-neutral theories of knowledge lead to the eclipse of the public realm and the growth of social regimentation, mass manipulation, large-scale indoctrination and totalitarian domination. As a result, the homo politicus is reduced to the homo faber and the animal laboran. What is required is a radical shift in our intellectual perspective. Phenomenological and linguistic-analytical theories of action are inadequate to provide a sound basis for political science. Philosphia perennis alone can restore to politics its full glory and splendor.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © University of Notre Dame 1985

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Notes

This is the revised version of the Presidential Address to the Thirty Eighth All Indian Political Science Conference held at Patiala, December 28-30, 1978. The author is grateful to his esteemed friend, Professor A. K. Saran, for his help in revising this essay for the present publication.

1 Easton, David, The Political System (Calcutta:Scientific Book Agency, n.d.), p. 146.Google Scholar

2 Lasswell, H., Political Writings of Harold Lasswell (New York: The Free Press of Glencoe, Inc., 1951).Google Scholar

3 Wright, Quincy, The Study of International Relations (New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1955).Google Scholar

4 Dahl, Robert A., Modern Political Analysis (Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, 1963), p. 6.Google Scholar

5 Easton, David, “The New Revolution in Political Science,” American Political Science Review, 63 (1969), 1052.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

6 Ibid., p. 1052.

7 Easton, , “Continuities in Political Research: Behaviouralism and Post-Be-haviouralism,”Google Scholar IPSA, VIII World Congress, Munich, September 1970.

8 Easton, , “The New Revolution in Political Science,” p. 1055.Google Scholar

9 Easton, , “Continuities in Political Research,” p. 11.Google Scholar

10 “Philosophy and Politics,” Unpopular Essays (London: Unwin Books, 1968), p. 20.Google Scholar

11 “On Scientific Method in Philosophy” Mysticism and Logic (London: Pelican Books, 1953), p. 106Google Scholar. “On questions of fact,” says Russell, “we can appeal to science and scientific methods of observations, but on ultimate questions of ethics there seems to be nothing analogous” (History of Western Philosophy [New York: Simon and Schuster, 1945], p. 116).Google Scholar

12 Kelsen, , What Is Justice? (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1957), pp. 2122.Google Scholar

13 Brecht, Arnold, Political Theory: Foundations of Twentieth Century Political Thought (Times of India Press, 1965).Google Scholar

14 Ibid., p. 161.

15 Ibid., p. 550.

16 Ibid., p. 337.

17 Ibid., p. 368.

18 See MacIntyre, A. C., “Hume on ‘is’ and ‘ought,’Philosophical Review, 68 (1959)Google Scholar; Atkinson, R. F., “Hume on ‘is’ and ‘ought’: A Reply to Mr. MacIntyre,” Philosophical Review, 70 (1961)CrossRefGoogle Scholar and other essays collected in Hudson, W. D., ed., The Is/Ought Question (London: Macmillan, 1969).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

19 Gellner, , “Contemporary Thought and Politics,” Philosophy, 32 (1957).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

20 Macdonald, Margaret, “Natural Rights” in Laslett, P., ed., Philosophy Politics and Society (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1956).Google Scholar

21 The viewpoint presented here may be contrasted with some well-known recent attempts to derive the “Ought” from the “Is.” Special mention should be made of J. R. Searle's famous paper, “How to derive ‘ought’ from ‘is,’” Philosophical Review, 73 (1964)Google Scholar, which sparked off much controversy in philosophical journals. See also Max Black's paper, “The Gap between ‘is’ and ‘should,’” Philosophical Review, 73 (1964)Google Scholar. For a criticism of Searle, see Flew, Antony, “On not deriving ‘ought’ from ‘is,’” Analysis, 25 (1964)Google Scholar. These and other relevant papers are collected in Hudson, The Is/Ought Question. Searle's attempt to derive “Ought” from “Is” is inspired by Miss Anscombe's distinction between “brute facts” and “institutional reality” and Austin's concept of “performative utterances.” He starts with such notions as “promising,” “paying one's debt,” etc., and proceeds to argue that institutional facts exist within systems of constitutive rules, systems of constitutive rules involve obligations, commitments and responsibility and within these systems one can derive “Ought” from “Is.” But he forgets that notions like promising are not brute facts. They are basically normative. Hence his attempt to derive “norms” from “facts” becomes a question-begging exercise.

22 Saran, A. K., “Some Aspects of Positivism in Sociology,” Transactions of the Fifth World Congress of Sociology (Washington, D.C., 2–8 09 1962), 1:231.Google Scholar

23 Nagel, Ernest, The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation (New York, 1961), p. 493.Google Scholar

24 Quoted by Sheridan, Alan, Michel Foucault: The Will to Truth (London: Tavistock Publications, 1980), p. 207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

25 “It is generally believed,” says Heisenberg, “that our science is empirical and that we draw our concepts and our mathematical constructs from empirical data. If this was the whole truth, when entering into a new field we should introduce only such quantities as can be directly observed and formulate natural law only by means of these quantities. When I was a young man I believed that this was just the philosophy which Einstein followed in his theory of relativity. But when I later asked Einstein about it, he answered: ‘This may have been my philosophy but it is nonsense all the same. It is never possible to introduce only observable quantities in theory. It is theory which decides what can be observed.’ What he meant by this remark is that when we go from immediate observation to the phenomena we are interested in, we must make use of theory and of theoretical concepts. We cannot separate the empirical process of observation from the mathematical constructs and its concepts.” “Tradition in Science,” The American Review, Summer, 1974.Google Scholar

Anatol Rapoport has observed that Galileo's theory of falling bodies is not an empirical theory. It is normative. “It described not how bodies fall, but how they ought to fall under idealized conditions. In this sense one can well see how a theory can be normative, yet truly scientific. The idea of a truly scientific theory of action is not to pontificate about morality, but to prescribe a correct course of action on the basis of a given desiderata, in certain (usually idealized) conditions” (“Various Meanings of Theory,” American Political Science Review, 52 [1958], 983).Google Scholar

26 For a profound analysis of this point see Saran, A. K., “A Prolegomenon to Nuclear Disarmament and World Peace,” Gandhi Marg, Vol. IV, Nos. 2 and 3, 0506 1982, pp. 179–95Google Scholar. Also cf. Jonas, Hans, “The Practical Uses of Theory,” Social Research, 26 (1959), 141–42.Google Scholar

27 This was first enunciated by Hempel in a classic paper entitled “The Function of General Laws in History,” Journal of Philosophy, 1942, and was further elaborated in a series of essays.Google Scholar

28 Marcuse, Herbert, One-Dimensional Man (ABACUS), 1972, p. 130.Google Scholar

29 Jonas, , “The Practical Uses of Theory,” pp. 141–42.Google Scholar

30 Cf. Marcuse, , One-Dimensional ManGoogle Scholar, “True, the rationality of pure science is value-free and does not stipulate any practical ends: it is ‘neutral’ to any extraneous values that may be imposed upon it. But this neutrality is a positive character. Scientific rationality makes for a specific societal organization precisely because it projects mere form (or mere matter-here, the otherwise opposite terms converge) which can be bent to practically all ends. Formalization and functionalization are, prior to all application, the ‘pure form’ of a concrete societal practice. While science freed nature from inherent ends and stripped matter of all but quantifiable quantities, society freed man from the ‘natural,’ hierarchy of personal dependence and related them to each other in accordance with quantifiable qualities—namely, as units of abstract labor power, calculable in units of time” (pp. 128–29).

31 Lasswell, Harold, Psychopathology and Politics (Chicago, 1930), pp. 196–97.Google Scholar

32 The Political Writings of Harold D. Lasswell (New York: The Free Press of Glencoe, Inc., 1951), pp. 524–25.Google Scholar

33 Storing, Herbert J., ed., Essays in the Scientific Study of Politics (New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston., Inc., 1962), p. 299.Google Scholar

34 Simon, Herbert, Models of Man (New York, 1957), p. 199.Google Scholar

35 Simon, Herbert, Administrative Behavior, 2nd ed. (New York, 1957).Google Scholar

36 Ibid., p. 102.

37 Simon, , Smithburg, and Thompson, , Public Administration (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1950), p. 22.Google Scholar

38 Modern discussions on counterfactual conditionals owe much to the classic papers of Chisholm and Goodman: Chisholm, R. M., “The Contrary to Fact Conditional,” Mind, 1946Google Scholar; Goodman, Nelson, “The Problem of Counter-factual Conditionals,” Journal of Philosophy, 1947Google Scholar. Since then the problem has been a subject of extensive discussion. For some recent discussions see Sosa, E., ed., Causation and Conditionals (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1975).Google Scholar

39 von Wright, George Henrik, Explanation and Understanding (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1971), p. 22.Google Scholar

40 Ibid., p. 21.

41 Voegelin, Eric, The New Science of Politics (Chicago, 1952), p. 27.Google Scholar

42 Oakshott, Michael, On Human Conduct (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), p. 97.Google Scholar

43 Waismann, F., “Language Strata” in Flew, , ed. Logic and Language, 2nd series (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1955).Google Scholar

44 Winch, Peter, The Idea of Social Science and its Relations to Philosophy (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1958)Google Scholar; Meldon, A. I., Free Action, (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1961)Google Scholar; Louch, A. R., Explanation and Human Action (Berkeley and Los Angeles: Univeristy of California Press, 1966)Google Scholar. Geach, Peter, Mental Acts (New York: Humanities Press, 1957)Google Scholar; Oakeshott, M., On Human Conduct (1975)Google Scholar; Taylor, Charles, Explanation of Behaviour (New York: Humanities Press, 1964)Google Scholar; Arendt, Hannah, The Human Condition (Garden City, New York: Doubleday & Company, Inc., 1959).Google Scholar

45 Anscombe, G. E. M., Intention (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1958)Google Scholar; von Wright, , Explanation and Understanding.Google Scholar

46 Nicholson, R. A., Rumi (London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd., 1950), p. 159, note 6Google Scholar. Anand K. Coomaraswamy admirably presents the traditional doctrine of freedom and necessity in these words: “The traditional doctrine is one of Fate and Free will, and must be so, just because there are ‘two in us,’ one fatally determined and the other free. Of these two, to have become what we are is to have risen above our fate. The chain of fate can never be broken, but we can break away from it to become its spectator, no longer its victim” (Coomaraswamy, Selected Papers, ed. Lipsey, Roger, Vol. 2 [Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1977], 369).Google Scholar

47 Aquinas: Selected Political Writings, edited with an Introduction by D'entreves, A. P. and translated by Dawson, J. G. (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1954), p. 197.Google Scholar

48 Thomas, St., Commentary on Aristotle's Nicomachean EthicsGoogle Scholar, quoted by Pieper, Josef, Happiness and Contemplation (London: Faber and Faber, 1958), p. 99.Google Scholar