Article contents
Why and how should we go for a multicausal analysis in the study of foreign policy? (Meta-)theoretical rationales and methodological rules
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 01 March 2011
Abstract
This article argues that International Relations (IR) researchers concerned with why-questions about the state's external behaviour ought to employ a multicausal approach attentive to the interrelated relationship between external structures and internal agents, presenting the (meta-)theoretical rationales underlying its argument. Here the author suggests ‘a rich/bold ontology’ regarding foreign policy behaviour. Then the article elaborates on detailed and explicit guidelines on how to traverse the bridge that connects the insights of that rich ontology to the empirical research necessary to make claims about the real world of any one moment. In a related vein, the article claims that a multicausal approach should be established using what the author calls ‘loose-knit deductive reasoning’ through which epistemological and methodological openness can be preserved in a manageable way. More importantly, this article discusses the role of theory for IR scholarship and the standards for judging theoretical contributions and progress in the field of IR. Ultimately, the author argues that a complex and flexible approach – both as a useful mode of explanation and as a progressive model of theory construction – can make important contributions to a better understanding of foreign policy and world politics, not only because it enables researchers to become keenly sensitive to the complex reality underlying a nation's foreign policy and to the interrelated relationship between structures and agents in international relations, but also because it can serve to provide a secure base for the progressive accumulation of the evidence closely associated with multiple causation on which any adequate explanation about complex foreign policy behaviour must surely be founded and without which general theory cannot really flourish.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © British International Studies Association 2010
References
1 Marsh, David and Furlong, Paul, ‘A Skin not a Sweater: Ontology and Epistemology in Political Science’, in Marsh, David and Stoker, Gerry (eds), Theory and Methods in Political Science (New York: Palgrave McMillan, 2002), p. 21CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
2 Wæver, Ole, ‘The Rise and Fall of the Interparadigm Debate’, in Smith, Steve, Booth, Ken and Zalewski, Marysia (eds), International Theory; Positivism and Beyond (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996)Google Scholar .
3 Walt, Stephen, ‘International relations: One world, many theories’, Foreign Policy, 110:1 (1998), pp. 29–46CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
4 Smith, Steve, ‘Diversity and Disciplinarity in International Relations Theory’, in Dunne, Tim, Kurki, Milja, Smith, Steve (eds), International Relations Theories: Discipline and Diversity (Oxford University Press 2007), pp. 4–9Google Scholar . Note, however, that in Europe, when comparing with the US IR scholarship, English School, constructivism, International Political Economy flourished to a much greater extent than realism in the 1980s and 1990s.
5 See, for example, Gilpin, Robert, US Power and the Multinational Corporation: The Political Economy of Foreign Direct Investment (New York: Basic Books, 1975)CrossRefGoogle Scholar ; Waltz, Kenneth N., Theory of International Politics (New York: Random House, 1979)Google Scholar , Waltz, Kenneth N., ‘Structural Realism after the Cold War’, International Security, 25:1 (2000), pp. 5–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar ; Wohlforth, William C., ‘The Stability of a Unipolar World’, International Security, 24:2 (1999), pp. 5–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar ; Mearsheimer, John, The Tragedy of Great Power Politics (New York: W. W. Norton, 2001)Google Scholar ; Layne, Christopher, ‘A New Grand Strategy’, The Atlantic Monthly, 289:1 (2002), pp. 36–42Google Scholar ; Layne, Christopher, ‘America's Middle East grand strategy after Iraq’. Review of International Studies, 35:1 (2009), pp. 5–25CrossRefGoogle Scholar ; Campbell, Craig, ‘American power preponderance and the nuclear revolution’, Review of International Studies, 35:1 (2009), pp. 27–44Google Scholar ; See also the 2009 special issue (no. 1) of World Politics in which nine authors explore the impact of the unipolar distribution of capabilities in the contemporary international system on the behaviour of the dominant state and on the reactions of other states.
6 See, for instance, the literature on the democratic peace theory including Maoz, Zeev and Russett, Bruce, ‘Normative and Structural Causes of the Democratic Peace’, American Political Science Review, 87:3 (1993), pp. 624–638CrossRefGoogle Scholar ; Russett, Bruce, Grasping the Democratic Peace: Principles for a Post-Cold War World (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993)Google Scholar . See also, for a useful critique of the democratic peace thesis, Barkawi, Tarak and Laffey, Mark (eds), Democracy, Liberalism, and War: Rethinking the Democratic Peace Debate (Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 2001)Google Scholar .
7 See, for example, Levy, Marc A., Young, Oran R. and Zürn, Michael, ‘The study of international regimes’, European Journal of International Relations, 1:3 (1995), pp. 267–331CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
8 See, for example, Keohane, Robert O. and Nye, Joseph S., Power and Interdependence: World Politics in Transition (Boston: Little, Brown and Company, 1977)Google Scholar .
9 On this point, see Crawford, Neta C., ‘The Passion of World Politics Propositions on Emotion and Emotional Relationships’, International Security, 24:4 (2000), pp. 116–156CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
10 Hay, Colin, Political Analysis: A Critical. Introduction (New York: Palgrave, 2002), p. 19CrossRefGoogle Scholar ; Kegley, Charles W. (ed.), Controversies in International Relations Theory (New York: St. Martin Press, 1995)Google Scholar .
11 Wendt, Alexander, Social Theory of International Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999)CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
12 Ibid., p. 113.
13 Wight, Colin, Agents, Structures and International Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), p. 92CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
14 Hudson, Valerie M., ‘Foreign Policy Analysis: Actor-Specific Theory and the Ground of International Relations’, Foreign Policy Analysis, 1:1 (2005), p. 9CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
15 Waltz, , Theory of International Politics, p. 117Google Scholar .
16 Morgenthau, Hans J., Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1948), p. 6Google Scholar .
17 Morgenthau, , Politics Among Nations, p. 5Google Scholar .
18 See, for example, Lobell, and his colleagues' edited book, Neoclassical Realism, the State, and Foreign Policy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
19 Tang, Shiping, ‘Taking Stock of Neoclassical Realism’, International Studies Review, 11:4 (2009), p. 802CrossRefGoogle Scholar . Much the same can be said about the works of a Realist-Liberal synthesis. See, for example, Papayoanou's 1996 articles on economic interdependence, domestic institutions, and the balance of power. Papayoanou, Paul A., ‘Interdependence, Institutions, and the Balance of Power: Britain, Germany, and World War I’, International Security, 20:2 (1996), pp. 42–76CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
20 Rose, Gideon, ‘Neoclassical Realism and Theories of Foreign Policy’, World Politics, 51:1 (1998), p. 151CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
21 Ruth, Lane, ‘Concrete Theory: An Emerging Political Method’, American Political Science Review, 84:4 (1990), pp. 927–940Google Scholar .
22 Rosati, Jerel A., ‘The Power of Human Cognition in the study of World Politics’, International Studies Review, 2:3 (2000), p. 45CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
23 Simon, Herbert, Models of bounded rationality (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1982)Google Scholar .
24 Lukes, Steven and Hollis, Martin, Rationality and Relativism (Oxford: Blackwell, 1982)Google Scholar .
25 Crawford, ‘The Passion of World Politics Propositions on Emotion and Emotional Relationships’, p. 116.
26 For more on this, see Jensen, Lloyd, Explaining Foreign Policy (NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1982), pp. 10–12Google Scholar ; Neack, Laura, The New Foreign Policy: US and Comparative Foreign Policy in the 21st Century (Rowman and Littlefield, 2003), pp. 8–15Google Scholar .
27 Checkel, Jeffrey, ‘The Constructivist Turn in International Relations Theory’, World Politics, 50:1 (1998), p. 339CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
28 Jervis, Robert, ‘Nuclear Weapons, Explaining the non-Realist Politics of the Bush Administration and US Military Presence in Europe’, Theory Talks, 12 (2008), p. 3Google Scholar .
29 They include cognitive consistency theory, schema theory and cognitive mapping. For a useful exploration of subtle differences among them, see Young, Michael D. and Schafer, Mark, ‘Is There Method in Our Madness? Ways of Assessing Cognition in International Relations’, Mershon International Studies Review, 42:1 (1998), pp. 63–96CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
30 Sprout, Harold and Sprout, Margaret, The Ecological Perspective on Human Affairs (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1965)Google Scholar . See also, Larson, Deborah Welch, ‘The Role of Belief Systems and Schemas in Foreign Policy Decision-Making’, Political Psychology, 15:1 (1994), pp. 17–33CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
31 Little, Daniel, Varieties of Social Explanation (Boulder: Westview Press, 1991), p. 183Google Scholar .
32 Rosati, ‘The Power of Human Cognition’, p. 47.
33 Patomäki, Heikki and Wight, Colin, ‘After Post-Positivism? The Promises of Critical Realism’, International Studies Quarterly, 44:4 (2000), p. 231CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
34 Weber, Max, Economy and Society (New York: Bed Minster Press, 1968), p. 13Google Scholar .
35 Wight, , Agents, Structures and International Relations, p. 98Google Scholar .
36 Hay, , Political Analysis, p. 125Google Scholar .
37 Laszlo, Ervin, The Systems View of the World: A Holistic Vision for Our Time (Hampton Press 1996), pp. 31–37Google Scholar .
38 Here I draw upon the insights of the ‘critical realist philosophy’ of Roy Bhaskar (1978) and the ‘structuration theory’ of Anthony Giddens (1979). Although they draw different implications from the relationship between structure and agent, they share the common ontological core: structures and agents in the social world are internally related. See Giddens, , Central Problems in Social Theory: Action, Structure and Contradiction in Social Analysis (London: Macmillan, 1979)CrossRefGoogle Scholar ; Bhaskar, , A Realist Theory of Science (Hassocks: Harvester Press, 1978)Google Scholar .
39 In this vein, rather than deterministic forces, the concept of cause in IR needs to be understood as ‘influences’ which do not have deterministic connotations: it is quite common for us to talk about someone exerting their influence but to no avail, so the concept of ‘influence’ does have a non-mechanistic meaning.
40 In this regard, I am against the position put forward by Hollis, Martin and Smith, Steve in ‘Two Stories about Structure and Agency’, Review of International Studies, 20:3 (1994), pp. 241–251CrossRefGoogle Scholar . See also, Hollis, Martin and Smith, Steve, ‘Beware of Gurus: Structure and Action in International Relations’, Review of International Studies, 17:4 (1991), pp. 393–410CrossRefGoogle Scholar . Their proposition that ‘there are always two stories to tell about the agency-structure debate’ is an epistemological stance which is trapped into the positivists' narrow and mechanistic understanding of cause in which causes are treated as deterministic (‘pushing and pulling’) forces working only in a ‘when A, then B’ manner. This is problematic especially in the causal study of the state's behaviour in global politics given the fact that the state's foreign behaviour invariably derives from multiple sources operating in combination: recall the ontologically interrelated relationship between the agent and the structure. There are complexity and variety intrinsically involved in world political causality. For this reason, as already mentioned (see fn. 39), causes are understood here as ‘influences’ which do not have deterministic connotations. As regards how to conduct an empirical analysis with the non-mechanistic and broad conception of cause, I discuss in detail in the next section.
41 Certainly, there have been integrated studies on foreign policy and attempts to develop integrated theoretical frameworks. See, for example, Rosenau, James N., ‘Pre-theories and Theories of Foreign Policy’, in Farrell, Barry (ed.), Approaches in Comparative and International Politics (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1966)Google Scholar ; Brecher, Michael, The Foreign Policy System of Israel: Setting, Images, and Process (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1972)Google Scholar ; Mintz, Alex, ‘How Do Leaders Make Decisions?: A Poliheuristic Perspective’, The Journal of Conflict Resolution, 48:1 (2004), pp. 3–13CrossRefGoogle Scholar . Yet these studies are more in the nature of exceptional examples rather than representative cases in a generally accepted research method in the field of IR.
42 Hermann, Charles F., ‘Epilogue: Reflections on Foreign Policy Theory Building’, in Neack, Laura, Hey, Jeanne A.K., Haney, Patrick J. (eds), Foreign Policy Analysis: Continuity and Change in Its Second Generation (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1995), p. 247Google Scholar .
43 Wendt, Alexander, ‘The Agent-Structure Problem in International Relations Theory’, International Organization, 41:3 (1987), p. 340CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
44 See, for studies of this kind, Putnam, Robert D., ‘Diplomacy and Domestic Politics: The Logic of Two-Level Games’, International Organization, 42:3 (1988), pp. 427–460CrossRefGoogle Scholar ; Mesquita, Bruce Bueno De and Lalman, David, War and Reason (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1992)Google Scholar ; Fearon, James D., ‘Domestic Political Audiences and the Escalation of International Disputes’, American Political Science Review, 88:3 (1994), pp. 577–592CrossRefGoogle Scholar ; Milner, Helen, Interests, Institutions, and Information (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1997)Google Scholar ; Auerswald, David, Disarmed Democracies: Domestic Institutions and the Use of Force (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2000)CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
45 Wittkopf, Eugene R., Jones, Christopher M., Kegley, Charles W., American Foreign Policy. Pattern and Process (Thomson Wadsworth 2008), p. 19Google Scholar .
46 See, for example, Jensen, Explaining Foreign Policy Holsti, Ole R., ‘Theories of International Relations and Foreign Policy: Realism and Its Challenges’, in Kegley, Charles W. (ed.), Controversies in International Relations Theory (New York: St. Martin Press, 1995)Google Scholar ; Neack, Laura, The New Foreign Policy: US and Comparative Foreign Policy in the 21st Century (Rowman and Littlefield 2003)Google Scholar ; Hudson, ‘Foreign Policy Analysis’, pp. 189–90; Wittkopf, et al. , American Foreign Policy, pp. 18–19Google Scholar .
47 See, for example, Kurki, Milja, Causation in International Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008)CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
48 For a similar critique, see Hall, Ian, ‘What Causes What: The Ontologies of Critical Realism’, International Studies Review, 11:4 (2009), pp. 629–630CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
49 Rob Stones notes that those engaged in a strict and formal form of deductive logic, known as ‘deductive-nomological’ modelling tend to write in an all-knowing, somewhat ‘omnipotent’ manner about events, but this implied knowledge is not matched by the levels of such confidence. See Stones, , Sociological Reasoning (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 1996), p. 83CrossRefGoogle Scholar . Going a step further, Robert Jervis comments that even scholars who use large N clusters of data ‘often look at many cases to see if a proposed generalisation fits the data. [But] this is a form of confirmation, not the discovery of new facts’. See Jervis, ‘Pluralistic Rigor’, p. 146.
50 Kurki, , Causation in International Relations, p. 45Google Scholar .
51 Patomäki and Wight, ‘After Post-Positivism?’, p. 217.
52 Carlsnaes, Walter, ‘The Agency-Structure Problem in Foreign Policy Analysis’, International Studies Quarterly, 36:3 (1992), p. 256CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
53 See, for a fuller exposition of this point, Sayer, Andrew, Method in Social Science: A Realist Approach (London: Hutchinson, 1984), pp. 105–111CrossRefGoogle Scholar ; Bhaskar, , A Realist Theory of Science, pp. 162–166Google Scholar .
54 Papayoanou, ‘Interdependence, Institutions, and the Balance of Power’, p. 44.
55 Jervis, Robert, System Effects: Complexity in Political and Social Life (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press), p. 295Google Scholar .
56 Here no attempt is made to provide a comprehensive list of all possible causal variables of states' external behaviour; many possible causal factors have already been described in previous works (see, for example, Rosenau, Pre-theories; Brecher, The Foreign Policy System of Israel). There is no need to recount them here. As noted, my intention in this article is to elaborate on how to utilise a multicausal approach and to make clear what ontological and epistemological assumptions and premises should be made before using it.
57 For classic illustrations of this method, see George, Alexander L., ‘The “Operational Code”: A Neglected Approach to the Study of Political Leaders and Decision-making’, International Studies Quarterly, 13:2 (1969), pp. 190–222CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
58 George, Alexander L., ‘The Causal Nexus between Cognitive Beliefs and Decision-Making Behavior: The Operational Code Belief System’, in Falkoswki, L.S. (ed.), Psychological Models in International Politics (Boulder: Westview Press, 1979), pp. 95–124Google Scholar . See also, Larson, Deborah Welch, ‘The Role of Belief Systems and Schemas in Foreign Policy Decision-Making’, Political Psychology, 15:1 (1994), pp. 17–33CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
59 For example, see Waltz, , The Logic of Comparative Social Inquiry (Malabar, Fla.: Krieger 1982)Google Scholar ; Ward, Hugh, ‘Rational Choice’, in Marsh, David and Stoker, Gerry (eds), Theory and Methods in Political Science (New York: Palgrave McMillan, 2002)Google Scholar ; Walt, Stephen, ‘The Relationship between Theory and Policy in International Relations’, The Annual Review of Political Science, 8 (2005), pp. 26–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
60 Kurki, Milja, ‘Causes of a divided discipline: rethinking the concept of cause in International Relations theory’, Review of International Studies, 32:2 (2006), p. 195CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
61 King, Gary, Keohane, Robert O., and Verba, Sidney, Designing Social Inquiry: Scientific Inference in Qualitative Research (Princeton: Princeton University, 1994), p. 101Google Scholar , emphasis in original.
62 Neurath, Otto, Philosophical Papers 1913–1946, trans. and eds Cohen, R. S. and Neurath, M. (Boston: Reidel, 1983), p. 92CrossRefGoogle Scholar .
63 George, Alexander L. and Bennett, Andrew, Case Studies and Theory Development in the Social Sciences (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2005)Google Scholar .
64 Yin, Robert K., Case Study Research: Design and Methods (London: Sage Publications, 2008), pp. 15–38Google Scholar . As a good example here, consider Graham Allison's original study of a single case, the 1962 Cuban Missile crisis which forcefully demonstrates how a single-case study can be the basis for significant explanations and generalisations. See Allison, Graham, Essence of Decision: Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis (Boston: Little, Brown, 1971)Google Scholar .
65 Brecher, Michael, ‘International Studies in the Twentieth Century and Beyond: Flawed Dichotomies, Synthesis, Accumulation, ISA Presidential Address’, International Studies Quarterly, 43:2 (1999), pp. 213–215CrossRefGoogle Scholar , emphasis added.
- 11
- Cited by