Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rcrh6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T15:38:13.808Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Right of entry or right of refusal? Hospitality in the law of nature and nations

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 November 2010

Abstract

This article explores the account of international hospitality found in the natural law tradition from Vitoria to Kant. Rather than limit itself to intellectual history, the focus here is on a more enduring theme: the double-bind of hospitality which the natural lawyers encountered in seeking to find a place for the welcome of the foreigner in the ‘law of nations’. Although these thinkers agreed on a natural right of communication, this proved destabilising, even destructive, of the property claims by which hosts establish their domain as properly theirs in the first place. All struggled with this double-bind, though this took different forms, from the concern that the law of hospitality might thereby justify colonial appropriation to fears for how it could threaten sovereignty. Two thinkers arguably find a way out of the double-bind of right of communication-right of property in hospitality, but sacrifice the law of hospitality in the process: Pufendorf, subordinating communication to property, turns hospitality into charity and thereby effectively denies it status as a law of nature; Kant, putting communication first, makes hospitality a matter of right, not philanthropy, but also sees it as instrumental to the development of a global civil condition, where it would be redundant.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © British International Studies Association 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Derrida, Jacques, Adieu: to Emmanuel Levinas, trans. P. Brault and M. Nass (Stanford CA: Stanford University Press, 1999)Google Scholar ; Derrida, Jacques, Of Hospitality, trans. R. Bowlby (Stanford CA: Stanford University Press, 2000)Google Scholar ; Derrida, Jacques, On Cosmopolitanism and Forgiveness, trans. M. Dooley and M. Hughes (London: Routledge, 2001)Google Scholar .

2 Pagden, Anthony, ‘Human Rights, Natural Rights, and Europe's Imperial Legacy’, Political Theory, 31:2 (2003), pp. 171199Google Scholar ; Cavallar, Georg, The Rights of Strangers: theories of international hospitality, the global community, and political justice since Vitoria (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2002)Google Scholar .

3 Montesquieu, Baron de, Complete Works, vol. 2 The Spirit of Laws (London: T. Evans, 1777 [1748]), pp. 144145Google Scholar .

4 Hume, David, Political Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994 [1748]), p. 122Google Scholar ; Smith, Adam, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (New York: Random House, 1994 [1776]), pp. 440441Google Scholar . However, see Rousseau for a characteristically contrary view to his enlightenment contemporaries. Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, The Levite of Ephraim, in Kelly, C. and Grace, E. (eds), Rousseau on Women, Love, and Family (Hanover NH: Dartmouth College Press, 2009 [1762]), pp. 178193Google Scholar .

5 Pagden, ‘Human Rights, Natural Rights’.

6 The emphasis on sociability obviously had a strongly theological dimension, as in Vitoria's argument that human communication and cooperation are God's will. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for this point.

7 Ibid., p. 184.

8 Ibid., p. 185. See also Tierney, Brain, The Idea of Natural Rights (Cambridge: Eerdmans, 1997), pp. 272 and 300301Google Scholar .

9 Pagden, ‘Human Rights, Natural Rights’, p. 186.

10 Ibid., pp. 186–7; Nussbaum, Martha, ‘Kant and Stoic Cosmopolitanism’, The Journal of Political Philosophy, 5:1 (1997), pp. 125CrossRefGoogle Scholar .

11 Pagden, ‘Human Rights, Natural Rights’, p. 186.

12 Cavallar, , The Rights of Strangers, p. 396Google Scholar .

13 Hunter, Ian, ‘Global Justice and Regional Metaphysics: On the Critical History of the Law of Nature and Nations’, in Dorsett, S. and Hunter, I. (eds), Law and Politics in British Colonial Thought: Transpositions of Empire (Houndmills: Palgrave/Macmillan, 2010), p. 1Google Scholar .

14 Ibid., p. 2.

15 Although our thinkers assume, or so I argue, something like these two ‘rights’, I am not claiming that these are the terms in which they couch their own arguments on hospitality. ‘Right of communication’ and ‘right of property’ is rather my own reconstruction of the key terms of the natural lawyers' various discussions of hospitality, as I read them. This reconstruction is then directed towards deconstructive rather than historical understanding – that is, I seek to draw out paradoxes at the heart of the thought of hospitality rather than to add to our knowledge of how this thought has been differently articulated in diverse spatio-temporal contexts. This deconstructive reading does not claim that hospitality is a transhistorical concept, but rather that otherwise very different answers to the question of how to receive the stranger nonetheless share an inability to harmonise the ‘communication’ and ‘property’ that all talk of hospitality always already assumes. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for encouraging me to clarify my point of departure.

16 Within the discipline, though instructively not in its mainstream, three recent exceptions to this rule stand out: Doty, Roxanne Lynn, ‘Fronteras Compasivas and the Ethics of Unconditional Hospitality’, Millennium, 35:1 (2006), pp. 5374Google Scholar ; Bulley, Dan, ‘Negotiating ethics: Campbell, ontopology and hospitality’, Review of International Studies, 32:4 (2006), pp. 645663Google Scholar ; and Onuf, Nicholas, ‘Friendship and Hospitality: some conceptual preliminaries’, Journal of International Political Theory, 5:1 (2009), pp. 121Google Scholar .

17 Onuf, ‘Friendship and Hospitality’ pp. 16–7.

18 Derrida, , On Cosmopolitanism, p. 16Google Scholar and Adieu, p. 50;

19 Vitoria, Francisco de, Political Writings (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 233Google Scholar .

20 Ibid., pp. 250, 243–6, 248, 250.

21 Ibid., p. 258.

22 Ibid., p. 264.

23 Ibid., p. 265. For an extended discussion of Vitoria's account of property, see Tierney, , The Idea of Natural Rights, pp. 260264Google Scholar .

24 Ibid., p. 278. Vitoria singles out language and friendship as indicating that human beings are meant for social life. He of course cites Aristotle's zoon politikon on this point (Tierney, , The Idea of Natural Rights, p. 291Google Scholar ).

25 Vitoria, , Political Writings, p. 278Google Scholar .

26 Ibid., p. 279.

27 Ibid., p. 280.

28 Ibid., p. 281.

29 Ibid., p. 281.

30 Ibid., p. 278.

31 Ibid., p. 278.

32 Ibid.

33 Ibid.

34 Ibid.

35 In Cavallar, , The Rights of Strangers, p. 111Google Scholar .

36 In Pagden, ‘Human Rights, Natural Rights’, p. 185. For more on the inhospitality of the conquistadores, see Baker, Gideon, ‘The Spectre of Montezuma: hospitality and haunting’, Millennium, 39:1 (2010)CrossRefGoogle Scholar .

37 Grotius, Hugo, ‘The Freedom of the Seas’, in van Holk, L. E. and Roelofsen, C. G. (eds), Grotius Reader (The Hague: T. M. C. Asser Instituut, 1983 [1609]), pp. 11, 6364, and 89 respectivelyGoogle Scholar .

38 Vattel, Emmerich de, The Law of Nations, trans. and ed. J. Chiity (New York: AMS Press, 1863 [1758]), p. 171Google Scholar .

39 Ibid.

40 Ibid.

41 Ibid.

42 Ibid.

43 Ibid., p. 173.

44 Ibid.

45 Ibid., p. 177.

46 Ibid., p. 1771.

47 Ibid., p. 179.

48 Ibid., p. 183.

49 Ibid., pp. 178, 180.

50 Ibid., p. 181.

51 Ibid., p. 178.

52 Ibid., p. 179.

53 Ibid., p. 183.

54 Ibid., pp. 179–80.

55 Ibid., p. 180.

56 This tension between property and communication continues in Vattel's discussion of rights of shelter held by exiled and banished peoples (see ibid., p. 180).

57 Ibid., p. 182.

58 Ibid., p. 184.

59 See, for example, ibid., p. 185.

60 Ibid., pp. 185–6.

61 Pufendorf, Samuel von, On the Law of Nature and Nations, trans. B. Kennett, ed. Barbeyrac (Clark, NJ: The Lawbook Exchange, 2005 [1672]), p. 244Google Scholar .

62 Ibid.

63 Cavallar, , The Rights of Strangers, p. 201Google Scholar .

64 Pufendorf, Samuel von, The Whole Duty of Man, According to the Law of Nature, trans. A. Tooke, ed. I. Hunter and D. Saunders (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 2003 [1691]), p. 50nGoogle Scholar .

65 Koskenniemi, Martti, ‘Miserable Comforters: International Relations as New Natural Law’, European Journal of International Realtions, 15:3 (2009), p. 397Google Scholar ; Ian Hunter, ‘Spatialisations of Justice in the Law of Nature and Nations: Pufendorf, Vattel and Kant’, unpublished research paper, available at: UQ e-space {http://espace.library.uq.edu.au/}, p. 23.

66 Pufendorf, , The Whole Duty of Man, pp. 128132Google Scholar .

67 Salter, John, ‘Grotius and Pufendorf on the Right of Necessity’, History of Political Thought, 26:2 (2005), pp. 284302Google Scholar .

68 Pufendorf, , On the Law of Nature and Nations, p. 208Google Scholar .

69 Pufendorf, , The Whole Duty of Man, p. 56Google Scholar .

70 Ibid., p. 104.

71 Pufendorf, , On the Law of Nature and Nations, pp. 243245Google Scholar .

72 Salter, ‘Grotius and Pufendorf’, p. 297.

73 Pufendorf, , On the Law of Nature and Nations, p. 245Google Scholar .

74 Cavallar, , The Rights of Strangers, p. 204Google Scholar .

75 Pufendorf, , On the Law of Nature and Nations, p. 245Google Scholar ; see also p. 246.

76 Ibid., p. 245.

77 Cavallar, , The Rights of Strangers, pp. 206207Google Scholar .

78 Pufendorf, , On the Law of Nature and Nations, p. 739Google Scholar .

79 Ibid., p. 245.

80 Ibid., p. 207.

81 Pufendorf, , The Whole Duty of Man, p. 50nGoogle Scholar .

82 Cavallar, , The Rights of Strangers, p. 205Google Scholar . In the case of the necessitous poor under civil law, Salter (‘Grotius and Pufendorf’) argues that Pufendorf's right of necessity does undermine the coherence of his distinction between perfect and imperfect right. But we are considering international law here, where, for Pufendorf, things are clearly very different.

83 Cavallar, , The Rights of Strangers, p. 204Google Scholar .

84 Thanks to Ian Hunter for drawing this to my attention.

85 Though see Koskenniemi (‘Miserable Comforters’, p. 399) for an opposing view here.

86 Pufendorf, , On the Law of Nature and Nations, p. 245Google Scholar ; see also p. 246.

87 Niesen, Peter, ‘Colonialism and Hospitality’, Politics and Ethics Review, 3:1 (2007), p. 92CrossRefGoogle Scholar .

88 Niesen, ‘Colonialism and Hospitality’, p. 92.

89 Kant, Immanuel, ‘Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch’, in Kant: Political Writings, trans. H. B. Nisbet and ed. H.S. Reiss (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 106Google Scholar .

90 See Derrida, , Adieu, p. 68Google Scholar ; Derrida, , Of Hospitality, pp. 27 and 7173Google Scholar ; Derrida, Jacques, ‘Hostipitality’, Angelaki, 5:3 (2000), pp. 34Google Scholar ; Derrida, : On Cosmopolitanism, pp 11, 22 and 27Google Scholar . For a contrary view, see Brown, Garrett W., ‘The Laws of Hospitality, Asylum Seekers and Cosmopolitan Right: a Kantian response to Jacques Derrida’, European Journal of Political Theory, 9:1 (2010)Google Scholar .

91 Kant, ‘Perpetual Peace’, p. 106.

92 Niesen, ‘Colonialism and Hospitality’, p. 94.

93 Kant, Immanuel, ‘The Metaphysics of Morals’, in Kant: Political Writings, trans. H. B. Nisbet and ed. H. S. Reiss (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 138Google Scholar .

94 Niesen, ‘Colonialism and Hospitality’, p. 94.

95 Kant, ‘The Metaphysics of Morals’, pp. 172–3.

96 Niesen, ‘Colonialism and Hospitality’, p. 95.

97 Ibid., pp. 98–100.

98 See, for example, Benhabib, Seyla, The Rights of Others: Aliens, Residents and Citizens (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), p. 38CrossRefGoogle Scholar .

99 Kleingeld, Pauline, ‘Kant's Cosmopolitan Law’, Kantian Review, 2:1 (1998), pp. 7390Google Scholar .

100 Benhabib, The Rights of Others. See also, Anderson-Gold, Sharon, Cosmopolitanism and Human Rights (Cardiff: University of Wales Press, 2001)Google Scholar .

101 Kant, ‘The Metaphysics of Morals’, p. 137.

102 Niesen, ‘Colonialism and Hospitality’, p. 101.

103 Ibid., p. 102.

104 Kant, ‘The Metaphysics of Morals’, p. 172.

105 Niesen, ‘Colonialism and Hospitality’, p. 102. Flikschuh, Katrin, Kant and Modern Political Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), p. 141Google Scholar . See also, Muthu, Sankar, ‘Justice and Foreigners: Kant's Cosmopolitan Right’, Constellations, 7:1 (2000), pp. 3435Google Scholar .

106 Niesen extends Flikschuh's ‘unilateral appropriation’ to include ‘colonial usurpation’. Unlike the former, the latter is not even in principle ratifiable in a global civil constitution and will instead have to be rectified.

107 Niesen, ‘Colonialism and Hospitality’, p. 103; Brown, Garrett W., ‘Kantian Cosmopolitan Law and the Idea of a Cosmopolitan Constitution’, History of Political Thought, 27:4 (2006), p. 664Google Scholar ; Flikschuh, Kant and Modern Political Philosophy.

108 Niesen, ‘Colonialism and Hospitality’, p. 103.

109 Kant, ‘Perpetual Peace’, p. 106.

110 Niesen, ‘Colonialism and Hospitality’, p. 105; cf. Hinsley, F. H., Power and the Pursuit of Peace (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1963)Google Scholar .

111 Derrida, ‘Hostipitality’, p. 4.

112 Hunter, , ‘Kant's Cosmopolitanism from a Historical Viewpoint’, in Hindess, B. and Walker, R. B. J. (eds), The Cost of Kant, forthcomingGoogle Scholar .

113 Ibid., p. 10.

114 Kant, Immanuel, ‘Critique of Practical Reason’, in trans. and ed. M. J. Gregor Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), p. 230Google Scholar .

115 Hunter, ‘Kant's Cosmopolitanism from a Historical Viewpoint’, p. 17.

116 Kant, in ibid., p. 17.

117 Hunter, ‘Kant's Cosmopolitanism from a Historical Viewpoint’, p. 11.

118 Ibid., p. 21.

119 Ibid., p. 23.

120 Kant, ‘Critique of Practical Reason’, p. 252.

121 Hunter, ‘Kant's Cosmopolitanism from a Historical Viewpoint’, p. 23.

122 Ibid., pp. 27–8.

123 Kant, ‘The Metaphysics of Morals’, p. 418.

124 Kant, ‘Perpetual Peace’, p. 106.

125 Derrida, , Adieu, p. 50Google Scholar ; Derrida, , On Cosmopolitanism, p. 16Google Scholar . For exemplary recent statements of hospitality as instrumental to cosmopolitan right from a Kantian perspective, see Brown, ‘Kantian Cosmopolitan Law’ and Brown, Garrett W., ‘Moving from Cosmopolitan Legal Theory to Legal Practice: Models of Cosmopolitan Law’, Legal Studies, 28:3 (2008), pp. 430451Google Scholar .

126 Kant, ‘Perpetual Peace’, pp. 106 (emphasis added) and p. 107.

127 Ibid., p. 107.

128 Ibid., pp. 107–8.

129 Ibid., p. 105.

130 Denis Diderot, Supplement to the Voyage of Bougainville, in Diderot:, DenisPolitical Writings, trans. and ed. J. H. Mason and R. Wokler (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992)Google Scholar . For an extended discussion of hospitality in Diderot's Supplement, see Klausen, Jimmy, ‘Of Hobbes and Hospitality in Diderot's Supplement to the Voyage of Bougainville’, Polity, 37:2 (2005), pp. 167192Google Scholar .

131 Onuf, ‘Friendship and Hospitality’.

132 Not that hospitality in world politics needs other than the inter- of the inter-national (a world of city-states, for example, would serve just as well as – better than, implies Derrida in On Cosmopolitanism – nation-states). Indeed, whether the figure of the foreigner, a figure which is necessary to the ethics of hospitality, requires territorialisation at all (that is, would hospitality indeed be redundant under conditions of cosmopolitan political community?) is a question for another occasion, one I consider in my book on hospitality in International Relations forthcoming with Routledge. My point here is simply to note the absence of hospitality from contemporary global imaginaries, including visions of cosmopolitan futures.