Article contents
Models of international organization in perpetual peace projects*
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 06 October 2010
Extract
Perpetual peace projects constitute a largely undervalued intellectual tradition that has attracted many polemical arrows. One of the most frequent criticisms levelled at the projects is that their authors too often abandon themselves to utopianism. Yet this tradition has proved to be much more influential than is generally recognized: contemporary international organizations, from the League of Nations to the United Nations, from the European Parliament to the International Court of Justice, were sketched out, if only in embryonic form, in these perpetual peace projects. Yet it is rare to find their authors numbered among the founders of internationalist theory.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © British International Studies Association 1992
References
1 Scheler, Max, ‘The Idea of Peace and Pacifism’, Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 7 (1976), pp. 154–66, and 8 (1977), pp. 36–50CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and Bobbio, Norberto, 11 problema delta guerra e le vie delta pace (Bologna, 1984) have presented actual taxonomies of pacifism, in which they distinguish between the finalistic, instrumental, juridical, etc. Projects for perpetual peace obviously belong to the latter category.Google Scholar
2 For a description and analysis of projects for peace, see ter Meulen, J., Der Gedanke der Internationalen Organisation in seiner Entwicklung, 3 vols. (The Hague, 1912, 1929, 1940)Google Scholar; Lange, C. and Schou, A., Histoire de I'internationalisme, 3 vols. (Oslo, 1919, 1944, 1954)Google Scholar; Hemleben, S. J., Plansfor World Peace through Six Centuries (Chicago, 1943)Google Scholar; von Raumer, K. (ed.), Ewiger Friede. Friedensrufe und Friedenspläne seit der Renaissance (Munich, 1953)Google Scholar; Hinsley, F. H., Power and the Pursuit of Peace (Cambridge, 1963)Google Scholar; Archibugi, D. and Voltaggio, F. (eds.), Filosofi per la pace (Rome, 1991).Google Scholar
3 Castel abbé de Saint-Pierre, C.-I., Abrégé du Projet de Paix Perpétuelle en Europe, (1729, English translation: London, 1927), 3° fundamental article.Google Scholar
4 Ibid. 4° fundamental article.
5 Ladd, William, An Essay on a Congress of Nations (London, 1840)Google Scholar; Jay, William, War and Peace (New York, 1842).Google Scholar
6 Crucé, Emeric, The New Cyneas (1623; English translation: Philadelphia, 1909), p. 110.Google Scholar
7 Ibid. p. 122. Saint-Pierre similarly maintained that sovereigns' powers would remain intact: ‘Most Members of the Union are absolute Kings or Princes who are totally bent on retaining absolute and completely independent sway over their Subjects’, Projet pour rendre la paix perpetuelle en Europe, (1713–17; reprinted: Paris, 1986), p. 234.
8 Crucé, The New Cyneas, p. 124.
9 Saint-Pierre, Projet pour rendre la paix perpetuelle en Europe, p. 166.
10 Although Sully attributes the ‘Grand dessin' wholly to Henry IV, it is uncertain to what extent is was actually thought up by the king, and to what extent it should be attributed to Sully's imagination alone. See Puharré, André, Les Projets d'organisation européenne d'apres le Grand Dessin de Henri IV et de Sully (Paris, 1954).Google Scholar
11 Kant, Immanuel, On the Common Saying: ‘This May be True in Theory, but it does not Apply in Practice’ (1793)Google Scholar, in Reiss, Hans (ed.), Kant's Political Writings (Cambridge, 1970), p. 92.Google Scholar
12 See Souleyman, E. V., The Vision of World Peace in Seventeenth and Eighteenth-Century France (New York, 1941).Google Scholar
13 Voltaire, , De la paix perpétuelle, par le Docteur Goodheart (London, 1769). § 1Google Scholar. On Saint-Pierre and Voltaire, see Perkins, M. L., ‘Voltaire and the Abbé de Saint-Pierre on World Peace’, Studies on Voltaire and the Eighteenth Century, 18 (1961), pp. 9–34.Google Scholar
14 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, ‘Jugement sur le projet de paix perpétuelle’ (1758), translated in The Political Writings of Jean-Jacques Rousseau (Oxford, 1962), p. 389.Google Scholar
15 Ibid. p. 396.
16 Ibid. p. 389.
17 Ibid.
18 French Revolution Documents (Oxford, 1966).Google Scholar
19 Cloots, A., La République universelle oil Adresse aux tyrannicides (Paris, 1793), reprinted in Œuvres, (Paris, 1980), p. 9.Google Scholar
20 In this regard, the diffused model ends up as a version of federalism. However, I will try to show that this is an unintended result, and not the starting point, of the authors I consider under this heading.
21 Penn, W., An Essay Towards the Present and Future Peace of Europe (1693, reprinted: London, 1950), § VII.Google Scholar
22 Ibid.
23 Ibid. § VIII.
24 Ibid.
25 Bellers, J., ‘Some Reasons for An European State’ (1710), reprinted in Clarke, G. (ed.), John Bellers, His Life Times and Writings (London, 1987), p. 141.Google Scholar
26 Saint-Simon, C.-H., ‘The Reorganization of the European Community‘ (1814), translated in Markam, F. (ed.), Social Organization, the Science of Man and Other Writings of Henri de Saint-Simon (New York and Evanston, 1964), p. 38.Google Scholar
27 Ibid. p. 50.
28 Ibid. p. 48.
29 Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals (1797), in Reiss, Kant's Political Writings, p. 171.
30 Saint-Simon, ‘The Reorganization of the European Community’, p. 50.
31 Bentham, Jeremy, Plan for an Universal and Perpetual Peace (1786–89; reprinted London, 1927), p. 35.Google Scholar
32 Saint-Simon, ‘The Reorganization of the European Community’, pp. 30–31.
33 For a recent analysis of Kant's writings on international relations, see Hurrell, A., ‘Kant and the Kantian Paradigm in International Relations’, Review of International Studies, 16 (1990), pp. 183–205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
34 Kant, , Perpetual Peace. A Philosophical Project, in Reiss, (ed.), Kant's Political Writings, pp. 93–7.Google Scholar
35 Cited in Hamilton, Alexander, Jay, John, Madison, James, The Federalist (1788, reprinted: Chicago, 1952), p. 87.Google Scholar
36 Kant, Perpetual Peace, pp. 98–105.
37 Ibid. p. 100.
38 From Fichte, J. G., ‘Zum ewigen Frieden. Ein philosophischer Entwurf von Immanuel Kant’ (1796), reprinted in Fichte, Gesamtausgabe, vol. 3 (Stuttgart, 1962)Google Scholar, to Galvano della Volpe, Rousseau and Marx (London, 1974)Google Scholar, democratic criticism of Kant's pacifist ideas has stressed this point.
39 According to some interpreters of Kant, cosmopolitan law is to be understood as ‘the relations of a state with the subjects of another state’; see Bobbio, N., Diritto e Stato in Emanuele Kant (Turin, 1969)Google Scholar. In fact, within the idea of cosmopolitan law, Kant includes the right of citizens to hospitality in foreign countries and opposition to colonialism. However, he also adds something far more interesting and fruitful for the purposes of transforming international relations, i.e. the separation of the law of nations from the law of individuals as citizens of the world.
40 For opposite interpretations of Kant's ideas a s ‘statist’ or ‘cosmopolitan’, see Hinsley, Power and the Pursuit of Peace, and Wight, Martin, ‘An Anatomy of International Thought’, Review of International Studies, 13 (1987), pp. 221–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
41 For a more detailed analysis of Kant's theory of international relations, and its relationship with the jus gentium tradition on the one hand, and the declarations of the rights of citizens of the French and the America n revolutions on the other, see D. Archibugi, ‘Immanuel Kant e il diritto cosmopolitico’, forthcoming in Giano. Ricerche per la pace.
42 Kant, Perpetual Peace, p. 108.
43 Among the applications of Kant's idea of cosmopolitan law, see Beitz, Charles, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton, 1979)Google Scholar, for economic rights, Linklater, Andrew, Men and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations (London, 1982)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, for individual obligations, Vincent, R. J., Human Rights and International Relations (Cambridge, 1986)Google Scholar with regard to the universality of some human rights, and Held, D. ‘Democracy, the Nation-State and the Global System’, in Held, (ed.), Political Theory Today (Cambridge, 1991), with regard to the implications for national democracy.Google Scholar
44 An overview of the current proposals to reform international organizations is provided in Barnaby, Frank (ed.), Building a More Democratic United Nations (London, 1991).Google Scholar
- 42
- Cited by