Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7czq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T11:17:48.696Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Between Banyans and battle scenes: Liberal norms, contestation, and the limits of critique

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 December 2015

Abstract

In studying the global spread and implementation of liberal norms, scholars have moved from linear notions of norm diffusion and promotion to an emphasis on norm contestation. Contestation by the supposed beneficiaries and addressees has taken centre stage in both research on the norms that underpin global governance and in studies on democracy promotion and liberal peacebuilding. While the impetus of this scholarship is normative – to overcome the taken-for-granted nature of liberal norms – the concept of contestation itself is mainly used with an analytical interest. Yet, as we show in this article, contestation also comes with – oftentimes implicit – normative connotations. Focusing on the seminal work of Milja Kurki, Oliver Richmond, Antje Wiener, and Amitav Acharya, we reconstruct these normative connotations. It turns out that the normative take on contestation is fairly conventional in all four approaches. Contestation is largely seen as a means to enable dialogue, as illustrated by Acharya’s metaphor of the Banyan tree. Fundamental conflicts over liberal norms (‘battle scenes’) are either not considered or seen as normatively undesirable. As a way forward, we propose a typology that enables scholars to empirically analyse contestation in its different expressions and suggest two strategies to normatively assess practices of contestation.

Type
Articles
Copyright
© 2015 British International Studies Association 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

Previous versions of this article were presented in August 2014 at the Fourth Global International Studies Conference in Frankfurt/Germany and in March/April 2014 in a Workshop on ‘Pragmatic Peacebuilding’ at the ECPR Joint Sessions in Warsaw/Poland. We thank Amitav Acharya, Pol Bargués Pedreny, Lothar Brock, David Chandler, Katja Freistein, Piki Ish-Shalom, Beate Jahn, Chris Hobson, Milja Kurki, Anton Peez, Oliver Richmond, the participants of the ‘Pragmatic Peacebuilding’ Workshop and three anonymous reviewers for helpful comments. Lisbeth Zimmermann acknowledges the support by the DFG funded Cluster of Excellence ‘Normative Orders’ at Goethe University Frankfurt am Main.

References

1 See Acharya, Amitav, ‘How ideas spread: Whose norms matter? Norm localization and institutional change in Asian regionalism’, International Organization, 58:2 (2004), pp. 239275CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Acharya, Amitav, Whose Ideas Matter? Agency and Power in Asian Regionalism (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Acharya, Amitav, ‘The R2P and norm diffusion: Towards a framework of norm circulation’, Global Responsibility to Protect, 5:4 (2013), pp. 466479CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Deitelhoff, Nicole and Zimmermann, Lisbeth, ‘Things we lost in the fire: How different types of contestation affect the validity of international norms’, PRIF Working Paper 18Google Scholar, available at: {http://www.hsfk.de/fileadmin/downloads/PRIF_WP_18.pdf} accessed 10 December 2013; Jetschke, Anja and Liese, Andrea, ‘The power of human rights a decade after: From euphoria to contestation?’, in Thomas Risse, Stephen C. Ropp, and Kathryn Sikkink (eds), The Persistent Power of Human Rights: From Commitment to Compliance (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), pp. 2642CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Wiener, Antje, ‘Contested compliance: Interventions on the normative structure of world politics’, European Journal of International Relations, 10:2 (2004), pp. 189234CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Wiener, Antje, The Invisible Constitution of Politics: Contested Norms and International Encounters (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Wiener, Antje, A Theory of Contestation (Berlin: Springer, 2014)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Zimmermann, Lisbeth, Global Norms with a Local Face? The Interaction of Rule of Law Promotion and Norm Translation in Guatemala (unpublished PhD thesis, Technische Universität Darmstadt, 2012)Google Scholar; Zimmermann, Lisbeth, ‘Same same or different? Norm diffusion between resistance, compliance, and localization in post-conflict states’, International Studies Perspectives (Online First: DOI:10.1111/insp.12080, 2014)Google Scholar; Zwingel, Susanne, ‘How do norms travel? Theorizing international women’s rights in transnational perspective’, International Studies Quarterly, 56:1 (2012), pp. 115129CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 See, among others, Bridoux, Jeff and Kurki, Milja, Democracy Promotion: A Critical Introduction (Abingdon: Routledge, 2014)Google Scholar; Chandler, David, ‘Peacebuilding and the politics of non-linearity: Rethinking “hidden” agency and “resistance”’, Peacebuilding, 1:1 (2013), pp. 1732CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Chandler, David and Richmond, Oliver, ‘Contesting postliberalism: Governmentality or emancipation?’, Journal of International Relations and Development, 18:1 (2015), pp. 124CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hobson, Christopher and Kurki, Milja (eds), The Conceptual Politics of Democracy Promotion (London: Routledge, 2012)Google Scholar; Kurki, Milja, ‘Democracy and conceptual contestability: Reconsidering conceptions of democracy in democracy promotion’, International Studies Review, 12:3 (2010), pp. 362386CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kurki, Milja, ‘Human rights and democracy promotion: Reflections on the contestation in, and the politico-economic dynamics of, rights promotion’, Third World Quarterly, 32:9 (2011), pp. 15731587CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kurki, Milja, Democratic Futures: Re-Visioning Democracy Promotion (Abingdon: Routledge, 2013)Google Scholar; Ginty, Roger Mac and Richmond, Oliver P., ‘Myth or reality: Opposing views on the liberal peace and post-war reconstruction’, Global Society, 21:4 (2007), pp. 491497CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ginty, Roger Mac and Richmond, Oliver P., ‘The local turn in peace building: a critical agenda for peace’, Third World Quarterly, 34:5 (2013), pp. 763783CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Poppe, Annika E. and Wolff, Jonas, ‘The normative challenge of interaction: Justice conflicts in democracy promotion’, Global Constitutionalism, 2:3 (2013), pp. 373406CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Richmond, Oliver P., ‘Resistance and the post-liberal peace’, Millennium, 38:3 (2010), pp. 665692CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Richmond, Oliver P., A Post-Liberal Peace (London: Routledge, 2011)Google Scholar; Richmond, Oliver P. and Mitchell, Audra, ‘Peacebuilding and critical forms of agency: From resistance to subsistence’, Alternatives, 36:4 (2011), pp. 326344CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Tadjbakhsh, Shahrbanou (ed.), Rethinking the Liberal Peace: External Models and Local Alternatives (London: Routledge, 2011)Google Scholar; Wolff, Jonas, Spanger, Hans-Joachim, and Puhle, Hans-Jürgen (eds), The Comparative International Politics of Democracy Promotion (London: Routledge, 2014)Google Scholar.

3 Kurki, , Democratic Futures, p. 4Google Scholar.

4 Richmond, , A Post-Liberal Peace, p. 149Google Scholar.

5 In this article, we do not use a fixed definition of liberal norms but relate more generally to the contested range of liberal conceptions of political order and (good) governance as used in contemporary international relations (the topic) and International Relations (the discipline) that include the set of norms associated with liberal models of democracy, rule of law, and human rights.

6 A liberal core of post-liberal peacebuilding research has, however, already been identified by postcolonial scholars. As Sabaratnam argues, post-liberal critiques are ‘trapped in a “paradox of liberalism”’. Sabaratnam, Meera, ‘Avatars of eurocentrism in the critique of the liberal peace’, Security Dialogue, 44:3 (2013), p. 270CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Chandler, David, ‘Resilience and the “everyday”: Beyond the paradox of “liberal peace”’, Review of International Studies, 41:1 (2015), pp. 3839CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Nadarajah, Suthaharan and Rampton, David, ‘The limits of hybridity and the crisis of liberal peace’, Review of International Studies, 41:1 (2015), pp. 4972CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7 This is part of Robert Cox’s famous definition of critical theory (as opposed to ‘problem-solving theory’). Cox, Robert W., ‘Social forces, states and world orders: Beyond International Relations theory’, Millennium, 10:2 (1981), p. 129CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 Acharya, ‘How ideas spread’; Epstein, Charlotte, ‘Stop telling us how to behave: Socialization or infantilization?’, International Studies Perspectives, 13:2 (2012), pp. 135145CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Krook, Mona L. and True, Jacqui, ‘Rethinking the life cycles of international norms: the United Nations and the global promotion of gender equality’, European Journal of International Relations, 18:1 (2012), pp. 103127CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Wiener, ‘Contested compliance’. For overviews of this scholarship, see Deitelhoff and Zimmermann, ‘Things we lost in the fire’; Zimmermann, Global Norms with a Local Face?; Zimmermann, ‘Same same or different?’.

9 Acharya, ‘How ideas spread’; Acharya, Whose Ideas Matter?; Acharya, Amitav, ‘Norm subsidiarity and regional orders: Sovereignty, regionalism, and rule-making in the Third World’, International Studies Quarterly, 55:1 (2011), pp. 95123CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10 See Rüland, Jürgen and Bechle, Karsten, ‘Defending state-centric regionalism through mimicry and localisation: Regional parliamentary bodies in the Association of Southeast Asian Nations (ASEAN) and Mercosur’, Journal of International Relations and Development, 17:1 (2014), pp. 6188CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Zwingel, ‘How do norms travel?’; and the overviews in Zimmermann, Global Norms with a Local Face?; Zimmermann, ‘Same same or different?’.

11 Wiener, ‘Contested compliance’; Wiener, The Invisible Constitution of Politics; Wiener, A Theory of Contestation.

12 See Krook and True, ‘Rethinking the life cycles of international norms’; Sandholtz, Wayne, ‘Dynamics of international norm change: Rules against wartime plunder’, European Journal of International Relations, 14:1 (2008), pp. 101131CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Van Kersbergen, Kees and Verbeek, Bertjan, ‘The politics of international norms: Subsidiarity and the imperfect competence regime of the European Union’, European Journal of International Relations, 13:2 (2007), pp. 217238CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13 Wiener, Antje, ‘The dual quality of norms and governance beyond the state: Sociological and normative approaches to “interaction”’, Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 10:1 (2007), pp. 4769CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

14 For overviews of this scholarship, see Mac Ginty, Roger (ed.), Routledge Handbook of Peacebuilding (Abingdon: Routledge, 2013)Google Scholar; Newman, Edward, Paris, Roland, and Richmond, Oliver P. (eds), New Perspectives on Liberal Peacebuilding (Tokyo: United Nations University Press, 2009)Google Scholar; Tadjbakhsh, Rethinking the Liberal Peace.

15 For overviews, see Bridoux and Kurki, Democracy Promotion; Hobson and Kurki, The Conceptual Politics of Democracy Promotion; Poppe and Wolff, ‘The normative challenge of interaction’.

16 See Mac Ginty and Richmond, ‘Myth or reality’; Mac Ginty and Richmond, ‘The local turn in peace building’; Richmond, Oliver P., The Transformation of Peace (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2005)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Richmond, Oliver P., ‘Patterns of peace’, Global Society, 20:4 (2006), pp. 367394CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Richmond, ‘Resistance and the post-liberal peace’; Richmond, A Post-Liberal Peace; Richmond and Mitchell, ‘Peacebuilding and critical forms of agency’.

17 Richmond, , ‘Patterns of peace’, p. 393Google Scholar; see also Richmond, The Transformation of Peace.

18 Kurki, ‘Democracy and conceptual contestability’. See also Hobson and Kurki, The Conceptual Politics of Democracy Promotion; Kurki, Democratic Futures.

19 Kurki, , Democratic Futures, p. 19Google Scholar.

20 Richmond, , A Post-Liberal Peace, pp. 1Google Scholar, 6, 12, 20, 130.

21 See Acharya, Amitav, ‘Global International Relations (IR) and regional worlds’, International Studies Quarterly, 58:4 (2014), pp. 647659CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Acharya, Amitav and Buzan, Barry (eds), Non-Western International Relations Theory: Perspectives on and beyond Asia (London: Routledge, 2010)Google Scholar.

22 Wiener, , A Theory of Contestation, pp. 89Google Scholar.

23 See Acharya, , ‘How ideas spread’, p. 242Google Scholar; Kurki, , ‘Democracy and conceptual contestability’, p. 363Google Scholar; Richmond, , A Post-Liberal Peace, pp. 45Google Scholar; Wiener, , ‘Contested compliance’, pp. 194200Google Scholar.

24 Wiener, , A Theory of Contestation, pp. 12Google Scholar, 1.

25 Ibid., p. 1.

26 For the overall debate, see Dunne, Tim and Flockhart, Trine (eds), Liberal World Orders (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Friedman, Rebekka, Oskanian, Kevork, and Pacheco Pardo, Ramon (eds), After Liberalism? The Future of Liberalism in International Relations (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan 2013)Google Scholar.

27 Kurki, ‘Democracy and conceptual contestability’. A second key move that characterises the research project at Aberystwyth is the deliberate turning away from a narrow, politico-institutional conception of democracy (and its contestation) towards a broader look at (contested) politico-economic models of democracy. See Bridoux and Kurki, Democracy Promotion; Kurki, ‘Democracy and conceptual contestability’; Kurki, ‘Human rights and democracy promotion’; Kurki, Milja, ‘Locating the normative within economic science: Towards the analysis of hidden discourses of democracy in international politics’, Journal of International Relations and Development, 16:1 (2013), pp. 5581CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hobson and Kurki, The Conceptual Politics of Democracy Promotion.

28 Kurki, Democratic Futures.

29 Ibid., p. 12.

30 Ibid.

31 See Gallie, W. B., ‘Essentially contested concepts’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56 (1956), pp. 167198CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

32 Kurki, Democratic Futures, p. 3.

33 Ibid., p. 4.

34 Ibid., p. 257, emphasis in original.

35 In this sense, Hobson and Kurki have explicitly put forward the ‘normative claim … that democracy promotion should be understood and practiced in a pluralist manner’. Hobson, Christopher and Kurki, Milja, ‘Conclusion: Reflections on a new approach in a new era of democracy promotion’, in Hobson and Kurki (eds), The Conceptual Politics of Democracy Promotion, p. 215Google Scholar, emphasis in original. See also Teivainen, Teivo, ‘The pedagogy of global development: the promotion of electoral democracy and the Latin Americanisation of Europe’, Third World Quarterly, 30:1 (2009), pp. 163179CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

36 See Dahl, Robert A., On Democracy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1998)Google Scholar; Diamond, Larry, ‘Three paradoxes of democracy’, Journal of Democracy, 1:3 (1990), pp. 4860CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Habermas, Jürgen, Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1996)Google Scholar.

37 Kurki, Democratic Futures, p. 28.

38 Ibid., p. 227.

39 Ibid., p. 242.

40 Ibid., p. 29.

41 Ibid., p. 256.

42 Generally speaking, the question whether a given conception of political – or politico-economic – order is explicitly called ‘democratic’ can hardly be used as a normative standard for selecting legitimate alternatives to liberal democracy. In the cases of Schmitt and Stalin, it would be difficult to dispute that their conceptions of political order are undemocratic, but this does only show that there has to be some kind of normative criteria for demarcating the field of contestation of democracy.

43 Kurki, , Democratic Futures, p. 263Google Scholar.

44 Hobson and Kurki, ‘Conclusion’, p. 221.

45 On this general problematique and the difficulty of distinguishing ‘between genuine opposition to Western imperialism and the cynical abuse of pro-democracy rhetoric by authoritarian regimes’, see Morozov, Viatcheslav (ed.), Decentring the West: The Idea of Democracy and the Struggle for Hegemony (Farnham: Ashgate, 2013)Google Scholar. The quotation is from the introduction: Viatcheslav Morozov, ‘Introduction: Locating international democracy’, in Morozov, Decentring the West, p. 15.

46 Kurki, Democratic Futures, ch. 12.

47 Richmond, , ‘Patterns of peace’, p. 393Google Scholar. See also Richmond, The Transformation of Peace.

48 Richmond, A Post-Liberal Peace, p. 58.

49 Ibid., pp. 58–9.

50 Ibid., p. 16.

51 Ibid., p. 117.

52 Ibid., p. 149. Richmond explicitly connects his discussion of resistance to peacebuilding to the larger debate about civil resistance, which clearly has a positive connotation. See Richmond, , A Post-Liberal Peace, p. 119Google Scholar.

53 Ibid., p. 29.

54 Ibid., pp. 184–5.

55 Ibid., p. 144.

56 Ibid., p. 107.

57 Ibid., p. 112.

58 Ibid., p. 215.

59 Ibid., p. 112.

60 Ibid., p. 207. At the same time, Richmond talks about the ‘opportunity for empathic relations to emerge between the international and the everyday’, which may be embedded in ‘a balancing framework for, say, Habermasian discourse ethics’. Richmond, , A Post-Liberal Peace, pp. 133134Google Scholar.

61 Ibid., p. 113.

62 Ibid., pp. 158–82.

63 Ibid., p. 145.

64 Ibid., p. 104, emphasis in original.

65 Ibid., p. 149. The normative benchmarks used by Richmond are correspondingly vague: ‘self-government, self-determination, empathy, care’; ‘self-government and self-determination’; or ‘participatory, empathetic, locally owned and self-sustaining, socially, politically, economically and environmentally speaking’. The overall aim is a version of peace that ‘would also provide justice and equity, and avoid violence both direct and structural’. Richmond, A Post-Liberal Peace, pp. 103, 105.

66 Ibid., p. 16.

67 Ibid., p. 15.

68 Ibid., p. 119.

69 Ibid., pp. 147–8.

70 Ibid., p. 132.

71 Ibid.

72 Wiener, A Theory of Contestation.

73 Wiener, ‘Contested compliance’; Wiener, ‘The dual quality of norms and governance beyond the state’; Wiener, The Invisible Constitution of Politics.

74 Wiener, A Theory of Contestation, p. 3. According to Tully’s multicultural democratic theory, contestation, also of a fundamental kind, is a basic principle of constitutional democracy shaped by diversity. Tully, James, ‘The unfreedom of the moderns in comparison to their ideals of constitutional democracy’, The Modern Law Review, 65:2 (2002), pp. 204228CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

75 Wiener, ‘Contested compliance’.

76 Wiener, , A Theory of Contestation, p. 1Google Scholar.

77 Wiener, , The Invisible Constitution of Politics, p. 4Google Scholar.

78 Ibid., p. 59.

79 Ibid., pp. 29–30; Wiener, Antje, ‘Normative baggage in international encounters: Contestation all the way’, in Oliver Kessler, Rodney Bruce Hall, Cecilia Lynch, and Nicholas Onuf (eds), On Rules, Politics and Knowledge: Friedrich Kratochwil, International Relations, and Domestic Affairs (Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2010), p. 203Google Scholar.

80 Wiener, A Theory of Contestation.

81 See also Vetterlein, Antje and Wiener, Antje, ‘Gemeinschaft revisited: Die sozialen Grundlagen internationaler Ordnung’,Leviathan, 41: Special Issue 28 (2013), pp. 78103Google Scholar.

82 Deitelhoff, Nicole, Überzeugung in der Politik (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 2006), pp. 126128Google Scholar.

83 Hansen-Magnusson, Hannes and Wiener, Antje, ‘Studying contemporary constitutionalism: Memory, myth and horizon’, Journal of Common Market Studies, 48:1 (2009), p. 39Google Scholar.

84 Wiener, , The Invisible Constitution of Politics, p. 31Google Scholar; Wiener, Antje and Puetter, Uwe, ‘The quality of norms is what actors make of it: Critical constructivist research on norms’, Journal of International Law and International Relations, 5:1 (2009), p. 7Google Scholar.

85 Wiener, ‘Contested compliance’, p. 218.

86 Wiener, , ‘Normative baggage in international encounters’, p. 202Google Scholar; Wiener, , A Theory of Contestation, p. 59Google Scholar.

87 Wiener, , The Invisible Constitution of Politics, p. 64Google Scholar.

88 Wiener, , ‘Normative baggage in international encounters’, p. 203Google Scholar.

89 Wiener, , A Theory of Contestation, p. 30Google Scholar.

90 Wiener aims at ‘a procedure to account for and identify different understandings and to develop sustainable agreements’ on global norms. See A Theory of Contestation, p. 43.

91 Ibid., pp. 64–5.

92 Wiener, , ‘Normative baggage in international encounters’, p. 203Google Scholar.

93 Wiener, , ‘The dual quality of norms and governance beyond the state’, p. 48Google Scholar.

94 Ibid., p. 56; Wiener, , The Invisible Constitution of Politics, pp. 204208Google Scholar; Wiener, A Theory of Contestation, pp. 53, 59.

95 Wiener, A Theory of Contestation, p. 53, emphasis in the original.

96 As far as we can see, Wiener also does not specify her understanding of the term ‘conflict’. See Wiener, ‘Normative baggage in international encounters’; Wiener, A Theory of Contestation.

97 Acharya, , ‘How ideas spread’, p. 241Google Scholar; see also Acharya, , ‘Norm subsidiarity and regional orders’, p. 118Google Scholar.

98 Acharya, Amitav, ‘Transnational civil society as agents of norm diffusion’, in Rodney Bruce Hall (ed.), Reducing Armed Violence with NGO Governance (Abingdon: Routledge, 2014), pp. 101Google Scholar. See also Acharya, ‘How ideas spread’; Acharya, Whose Ideas Matter?

99 Acharya, ‘Norm subsidiarity and regional orders’.

100 Acharya, , ‘How ideas spread’, p. 251Google Scholar; Acharya, , ‘Norm subsidiarity and regional orders’, p. 95Google Scholar.

101 This metaphor was specifically proposed in the context of human rights norm diffusion. See Amitav Acharya, ‘From the Boomerang to the Banyan: the Diffusion of Human Rights Norms Reconsidered, paper prepared for the Conference on Human Rights Futures’, Columbia University, New York, 15 November 2013, made available to us by the author; Acharya, ‘Transnational civil society as agents of norm diffusion’, p. 108.

102 Keck, Margaret E. and Sikkink, Kathryn, Activists Beyond Borders: Advocacy Networks in International Politics (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1998)Google Scholar.

103 Acharya, ‘Transnational civil society as agents of norm diffusion’, pp. 98–103. The same critique would apply also to the spiral model of international human rights diffusion, including its updated version. See Risse, Thomas, Ropp, Stephen C., and Sikkink, Kathryn (eds), The Power of Human Rights: International Norms and Domestic Change (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Risse, Thomas, Ropp, Stephen C., and Sikkink, Kathryn (eds), The Persistent Power of Human Rights: From Commitment to Compliance (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. In the latter volume, the contribution by Jetschke and Liese explicitly aims at correcting problematic ‘implicit assumptions of the spiral model’ by taking into account ‘the notion of counter-frames to human rights norms and contestation’ (Jetschke and Liese, ‘The power of human rights a decade after’, p. 27). Yet, in fact, they do not consider any meaningful possibility of norm contestation but only two types of normative responses – ‘justifications’ and ‘excuses’ – that do not involve any questioning of the validity of the norms themselves (Jetschke and Liese, ‘The power of human rights a decade after’, p. 36).

104 Acharya, , ‘Transnational civil society as agents of norm diffusion’, pp. 104108Google Scholar.

105 See also Acharya, ‘The R2P and norm diffusion’.

106 Acharya, ‘From the Boomerang to the Banyan’, p. 8.

107 Acharya, ‘Transnational civil society as agents of norm diffusion’; Acharya, ‘From the Boomerang to the Banyan’, p. 7.

108 Acharya, ‘From the Boomerang to the Banyan’, p. 21.

109 Ibid.; Acharya, ‘Transnational civil society as agents of norm diffusion’, p. 108.

110 Ibid., p. 108.

111 Acharya, ‘From the Boomerang to the Banyan’, p. 27.

112 Ibid.

113 Wiener does explicitly exclude ‘violent acts such as for example any form of war, terrorist acts or protest’ – but only because she defines contestation as a practice that ‘is always expressed through language’ (Wiener, A Theory of Contestation, p. 49). This, however, is in tension with the earlier statement that contestation ‘does not necessarily involve language’ (p. 1). In any case, contestation that includes a call for violent resistance would be part of the definition. The strong reference to Tully (see Tully, ‘The unfreedom of the moderns’) also suggests that Wiener does include contestation that questions norms and normative orders as such. Yet, again, such forms of contestation are not dealt with in her book.

114 See Held, David, Democracy and the Global Order. From the Modern State to Cosmopolitan Governance (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1995)Google Scholar; McGrew, Anthony, ‘Models of transnational democracy’, in David Held and Anthony McGrew (eds), The Global Transformations Reader: An Introduction to the Globalization Debate (Cambridge: Polity, 2003), pp. 500513Google Scholar.

115 See Thiel, Thorsten, ‘Im Zweifel für den Zweifel: Theoretische Perspektiven auf die Legitimität von Kritik in der postnationalen Konstellation’ (unpublished manuscript, Frankfurt: Goethe University, 2014)Google Scholar.

116 For just a glimpse at this debate, see Held, David, ‘Democratic accountability and political effectiveness from a cosmopolitan perspective’, Government and Opposition, 39:2 (2004), pp. 364391CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Nanz, Patrizia and Steffek, Jens, ‘Global governance, participation and the public sphere’, Government and Opposition, 39:2 (2004), pp. 314335CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Slaughter, Anne-Marie, ‘Disaggregated sovereignty: Towards the public accountability of global government networks’, Government and Opposition, 39:2 (2004), pp. 159190CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Young, Iris Marion, ‘Communication and the other: Beyond deliberative democracy’, in Seyla Benhabib (ed.), Democracy and Difference (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996), pp. 121135Google Scholar; Zürn, Michael, ‘Democratic governance beyond the nation-state: the EU and other international institutions’, European Journal of International Relations, 6:2 (2000), pp. 183221CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

117 Kuyper, Jonathan W., ‘The democratic potential of systemic pluralism’, Global Constitutionalism, 3:2 (2014), pp. 181182CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

118 Habermas, Between Facts and Norms.

119 See Gill, Stephen, Power and Resistance in the New World Order (Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2003)Google Scholar; Mouffe, Chantal, The Democratic Paradox (London: Verso, 2000)Google Scholar; Mouffe, Chantal, On the Political (London: Routledge, 2005)Google Scholar; Rancière, Jacques, Disagreement: Politics And Philosophy (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2004)Google Scholar; Rupert, Mark, ‘Globalising common sense: a Marxian-Gramscian (re-)vision of the politics of governance/resistance’, Review of International Studies, 29:S1 (2003), pp. 181198CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For an overview, see also Marchart, Oliver, Post-Foundational Political Thought: Political Difference in Nancy, Lefort, Badiou and Laclau (Edinburgh University Press, 2007)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

120 See Flügel-Martinsen, Oliver, ‘Demokratie und Dissens: Zur Kritik konsenstheoretischer Prämissen der deliberativen Demokratietheorie’, in Hubertus Buchstein (ed.), Die Versprechen der Demokratie (Baden-Baden: Nomos, 2013), pp. 333334CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

121 See also Nonhoff, Martin, ‘Demokratisches Verfahren und politische Wahrheitsproduktion: Eine radikaldemokratische Kritik der direkten Demokratie’, in Buchstein (ed.), Die Versprechen der Demokratie, p. 318Google Scholar.

122 See, for example, Gill’s concept of the postmodern prince. Gill, Power and Resistance in the New World Order. See also Hardt, Michael and Negri, Antonio, Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000)Google Scholar; Rancière, Disagreement.

123 Thiel, ‘Im Zweifel für den Zweifel’, p. 4; authors’ translation.

124 Mouffe, The Democratic Paradox; Mouffe, On the Political.

125 Daase, Christopher and Deitelhoff, Nicole, ‘Zur Rekonstruktion globaler Herrschaft aus dem Widerstand’, Internationale Dissidenz Working Paper 1 (2014)Google Scholar, available at: {http://dissidenz.net/workingpapers/wp1-2014-daase-deitelhoff.pdf} accessed 28 April 2014.

126 See Wiener, A Theory of Contestation, pp. 1, 49, fn. 113.

127 In a general sense, this is in line with what Boltanski calls a ‘sociology of critique’. Boltanski, Luc, On Critique: A Sociology of Emancipation (Cambridge: Polity, 2011)Google Scholar.

128 Deitelhoff and Zimmermann, ‘Things we lost in the fire’.

129 In Wiener’s terminology, the former type of contestation concerns ‘standardised procedures’, the latter ‘fundamental norms’, while ‘organising principles’ occupy an intermediate position. Wiener, A Theory of Contestation, p. 3.

130 See Daase and Deitelhoff, ‘Zur Rekonstruktion globaler Herrschaft aus dem Widerstand’; Tarrow, Sidney, Power in Movement: Social movements and Contentious Politics (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

131 The original quote reads: ‘There are no endogenous grounds in hegemony theory to differentiate between various hegemonies from the point of view of their emancipatory potential’. Morozov, ‘Introduction’, p. 10.

132 See Tully, John, An Approach to Political Philosophy: Locke in Contexts (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), p. 56CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

133 Hoy, David Couzens, Critical Resistance: From Poststructuralism to Post-Critique (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2005), pp. 238239Google Scholar.

134 See also Daase and Deitelhoff, ‘Zur Rekonstruktion globaler Herrschaft aus dem Widerstand’; Engelkamp, Stephan, Glaab, Katharina, and Judith, , ‘Office hours: How (critical) norm research can regain its voice’, World Political Science Review, 10:1 (2014), pp. 6189CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kurki, Democratic Futures, ch. 11.

135 The debates in philosophy centre on the question where such standards can be derived from distinguishing external, internal, and immanent critique. See, for example, Jaeggi, Rahel, ‘Towards an immanent critique of forms of life’, Raisons Politiques, 57:1 (2015), pp. 1329CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

136 Butler, Judith, ‘What is critique? An essay on Foucault’s virtue’, in David Ingram (ed.), The Political: Readings in Continental Philosophy (London: Basil Blackwell, 2002), pp. 212226Google Scholar; Mahon, Michael, ‘Michel Foucault’s archaeology, enlightenment, and critique’, Human Studies, 16 (1993), pp. 129141CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Saar, Martin, ‘Genealogische Kritik’, in Rahel Jaeggi and Tilo Wesche (eds), Was ist Kritik? (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 2009), pp. 247265Google Scholar.

137 Engelkamp, et al., ‘Office hours’; Sungju Park-Kang, ‘Utmost listening: Feminist IR as a foreign language’, Millennium, 39:3 (2011), pp. 861877Google Scholar.

138 Danius, Sara, Jonsson, Stefan, and Chakravorty Spivak, Gayatri, ‘An interview with Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak’, boundary 2, 20:2 (1993), pp. 2450CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

139 This overall guideline directly draws on David Couzens Hoy, who concludes his discussion of critical resistance by saying ‘that resistance that was unwilling to be both critical and self-critical would not even be worth attempting in the first place’. Hoy, Critical Resistance, p. 239.