Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rdxmf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T15:58:49.843Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The location of international practices: what is human rights practice?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 December 2012

Abstract

This article opens up space to challenge state-centrism about human rights practice. To do so, it presents and critically assesses four methods that can be used to determine who and/or what counts as a part of any international practice: the agreement method, which locates a practice by referring to speech acts that define it; the contextual method, which locates a practice by referring to the actions, meanings, and intentions of practitioners; the value method, which locates a practice by identifying a value or principle that the practice reflects or instantiates; and the purpose method, which locates a practice by constructing an account of the sociopolitical reason(s) for a practice's existence. The purpose method, based on an interpretation of Rawls' constructivism, is developed, in a way that focuses on practitioners' judgement-based reasons to assign responsibility for human rights to any state or non-state actor.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © British International Studies Association 2012 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Schatzki, Theodore R., Knorr Cetina, Karin, and von Savigny, Eike (eds), The Practice Turn in Contemporary Theory (London: Routledge, 2001)Google Scholar.

2 Adler, Emanuel and Pouliot, Vincent, ‘International Practices’, International Theory, 3:1 (2011), pp. 135CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 Ibid., p. 24.

4 Chris Brown mentioned this example in the panel on ‘Middle Ground Ethics in International Relations’ at the SGIR 7th Pan-European Conference on IR, Stockholm, Sweden (10 September 2010).

5 Rawls, John, ‘Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory’, Journal of Philosophy, 77:9 (1980), pp. 515–72Google Scholar. See also James, Aaron, ‘Constructing Justice for Existing Practice: Rawls and the Status Quo’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 33:3 (2005), pp. 281316CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 Pouliot, Vincent, ‘The Logic of Practicality: A Theory of Practice of Security Communities’, International Organization, 62:2 (2008), pp. 257–88CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Adler and Pouliot, ‘International Practices’.

7 Pouliot, ‘The Logic of Practicality’.

8 Rawls, John, The Law of Peoples with ‘The Idea of Public Reason Revisited’ (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999)Google Scholar; Beitz, Charles R., ‘Human Rights and the Law of Peoples’, in Chatterjee, Deen K. (ed.), The Ethics of Assistance: Morality and the Distant Needy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), pp. 102–24Google Scholar; Beitz, Charles R., The Idea of Human Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Raz, Joseph, ‘Human Rights Without Foundations’, in Besson, Samantha and Tasioulas, John (eds), The Philosophy of International Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), pp. 321–37Google Scholar.

9 Oakeshott, Michael, On Human Conduct (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1975)Google Scholar; Bourdieu, Pierre, Outline of a Theory of Practice, trans. Nice, Richard (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Nardin, Terry, Law, Morality, and the Relations of States (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1983)Google Scholar; MacIntyre, Alasdair, After Virtue (2nd edn, London: Duckworth, 1985)Google Scholar; Searle, John R., The Construction of Social Reality (London: Penguin, 1995)Google Scholar; Foucault, Michel, The History of Sexuality, trans. Hurley, Robert, 3 vols (London: Vintage, 1988–90)Google Scholar; Keck, Margaret E. and Sikkink, Kathryn, Activists Beyond Borders: Advocacy Networks in International Politics (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1998), p. 35Google Scholar; MacIntyre, Alasdair, ‘Social Structures and Their Threats to Moral Agency’, Philosophy, 74 (1999), pp. 311–29CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Guzzini, Stefano, ‘A Reconstruction of Constructivism in International Relations’, European Journal of International Relations, 6:2 (2000), pp. 147–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Schatzki, Cetina, and von Savigny (eds), The Practice Turn in Contemporary Theory; Neumann, Iver B., ‘Returning Practice to the Linguistic Turn: The Case of Diplomacy’, Millennium, 31:3 (2002), pp. 627–51CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Adler, Emanuel, ‘The Spread of Security Communities: Communities of Practice, Self-Restraint and NATO's Post Cold War Transformation’, European Journal of International Relations, 14:2 (2008), pp. 195230CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Pouliot, ‘The Logic of Practicality’; Hopf, Ted, ‘The Logic of Habit in International Relations’, European Journal of International Relations, 16:4 (2010), pp. 539–61CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Navari, Cornelia, ‘The Concept of Practice in the English School’, European Journal of International Relations, 17:4 (2011), pp. 611–30CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10 Adler, ‘The Spread of Security Communities’; Pouliot, ‘The Logic of Practicality’; Adler, and Pouliot, , ‘International Practices’; Adler, Emanuel and Pouliot, Vincent (eds), International Practices (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2011)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

11 Adler and Pouliot, ‘International Practices’, pp. 4–5.

12 Rawls says: ‘I use the word “practice” … as a sort of technical term meaning any form of activity specified by a system of rules which defines offices, roles, moves, penalties, defenses, and so on, and which gives the activity its structure.’ Rawls, John, ‘Two Concepts of Rules’, The Philosophical Review, 64:1 (1955), p. 3, fn. 1CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Beitz, The Idea of Human Rights, p. 105.

13 Pouliot, ‘The Logic of Practicality’.

14 Adler and Pouliot, ‘International Practices’.

15 Pouliot, ‘The Logic of Practicality’.

16 March, James G. and Olsen, Johan P., Rediscovering Institutions: The Organizational Basis of Politics (New York: Free Press, 1989), chap. 2Google Scholar; March, James G. and Olsen, Johan P., ‘The Institutional Dynamics of International Political Orders’, International Organization, 52:4 (1998), pp. 943–69, pp. 949–54CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17 Pouliot, ‘The Logic of Practicality’, pp. 260–65; Hopf, ‘The Logic of Habit’, pp. 549–51.

18 Surgeons especially can only be fully trained through practice; ‘practising’ medicine is a common expression.

19 Pouliot, ‘The Logic of Practicality’, pp. 265–78.

20 This list reflects that various narrower practices can be clustered inside of wider ones.

21 Kant, Immanuel, ‘An Answer to the Question: What Is Enlightenment?’, in Gregor, Mary J. (ed.), Immanuel Kant: Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996 [orig. pub.1784]), pp. 1722CrossRefGoogle Scholar; MacIntyre, ‘Social Structures and Their Threats to Moral Agency’.

22 Meckled-Garcia, Saladin, ‘Do Transnational Economic Effects Violate Human Rights?’, Ethics & Global Politics, 2:3 (2009), pp. 259–76CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

23 Berlin, Isaiah, Four Essays on Liberty (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1969), chap. 3Google Scholar. According to the ‘value method’, which I define and explain below – and which partly captures Berlin's own project – multiple practices might advance the same value. For example, redistribution through taxes in a capitalist liberal-democracy, on the one hand, and socialism, on the other, might both be thought of as ways to advance the value of positive liberty in practice.

24 Adler and Pouliot, ‘International Practices’, p. 6.

25 Wendt, Alexander, ‘On Constitution and Causation in International Relations’, Review of International Studies, 24:5 (1998), pp. 101–18CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

26 I also discuss the relationships between practices and their normativity in Karp, David Jason, ‘Facts and Values in Politics and Searle's Construction of Social Reality’, Contemporary Political Theory, 8:2 (2009), pp. 152–75CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

27 In this sentence, by ‘practice’, I mean doing things in the world, perhaps in a non-reflexive way that is formed by experience or habit, and by ‘a specific practice’, I mean patterned human activity with recognised social meaning and often (though not necessarily) a distinct label.

28 Sending, Ole Jacob, ‘Constitution, Choice and Change: Problems with the “Logic of Appropriateness” and its Use in Constructivist Theory’, European Journal of International Relations, 8:4 (2002), pp. 443–70CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

29 MacIntyre, ‘Social Structures and Their Threats to Moral Agency’.

30 Beitz, The Idea of Human Rights, pp. 13–47.

31 Ibid., p. 44.

32 Ibid., pp. 14–31.

33 Ibid., pp. 73–95.

34 Hart, H. L. A., The Concept of Law (2nd edn, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997 [orig. pub. 1961]), pp. 78123Google Scholar.

35 Simmons, Beth A., Mobilizing for Human Rights: International Law in Domestic Politics (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

36 Ratner, Steven R., ‘Corporations and Human Rights: A Theory of Legal Responsibility’, Yale Law Journal, 111:3 (2001), pp. 443545CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Alston, Philip (ed.), Non-State Actors and Human Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005)Google Scholar; Clapham, Andrew, Human Rights Obligations of Non-State Actors (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

37 John G. Ruggie, Protect, Respect and Remedy: A Framework for Business and Human Rights, A/HRC/8/5, Human Rights Council, UN General Assembly, 8th session (New York: United Nations, 2008), available at: {http://www2.ohchr.org/english/bodies/hrcouncil/8session/reports.htm} accessed 28 January 2011.

38 Babbitt, Susan E., ‘The Construction of Social Reality, John R. Searle’, The Philosophical Review, 106:4 (1997), pp. 608–10CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Jackson, Robert H., Quasi-States: Sovereignty, International Relations and the Third World (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), p. 178Google Scholar.

39 Simmons, A. John, Moral Principles and Political Obligations (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979), pp. 57100Google Scholar.

40 Brown, Chris, ‘Universal Human Rights: A Critique’, in Dunne, Tim and Wheeler, Nicholas J. (eds), Human Rights in Global Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), pp. 103–27CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

41 Lauren, Paul Gordon, The Evolution of International Human Rights: Visions Seen (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1998), pp. 94–8Google Scholar.

42 Skinner, Quentin, ‘Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas’, History and Theory, 8:1 (1969), pp. 353CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Pocock, J. G. A., Political Thought and History: Essays on Theory and Method (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008)Google Scholar. See also Ball, Terence, Farr, James, and Hanson, Russell L. (eds), Political Innovation and Conceptual Change (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1989)Google Scholar.

43 Finnemore, Martha and Sikkink, Kathryn, ‘International Norm Dynamics and Political Change’, International Organization, 52:4 (1998), pp. 887917CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Keck and Sikkink, Activists Beyond Borders; Risse, Thomas, ‘“Let's Argue!”: Communicative Action in World Politics’, International Organization, 54:1 (2000), pp. 139CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

44 Barnett, Michael, ‘Humanitarianism Transformed’, Perspectives on Politics, 3:4 (2005), pp. 723–40CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

45 Hopgood, Stephen, Keepers of the Flame: Understanding Amnesty International (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2006)Google Scholar.

46 Burgers, Jan Herman, ‘The Road to San Francisco: The Revival of the Human Rights Idea in the Twentieth Century’, Human Rights Quarterly, 14:4 (1992), pp. 464–70CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Lauren, Paul Gordon, The Evolution of International Human Rights: Visions Seen (2nd edn, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2003), pp. 135–65Google Scholar.

47 UNESCO (ed.), Human Rights: Comments and Interpretations (New York: Columbia University Press, 1949)Google Scholar.

48 Jackson, Patrick T., The Conduct of Inquiry in International Relations (New York: Routledge, 2011)Google Scholar.

49 Popper, Karl, The Logic of Scientific Discovery (London: Hutchinson, 1959)Google Scholar.

50 Sikkink, Kathryn, ‘The Role of Consequences, Comparison and Counterfactuals in Constructivist Ethical Thought’, in Price, Richard (ed.), Moral Limit and Possibility in World Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008), pp. 90–1Google Scholar.

51 Karp, ‘Facts and Values in Politics’.

52 Dworkin, Ronald, Law's Empire (London: Fontana, 1986), pp. 4586Google Scholar.

53 Berlin, Four Essays on Liberty, chap. 3.

54 See Dworkin, Law's Empire, pp. 176–244; Dworkin, Ronald, ‘Do Liberal Values Conflict?’, in Lilla, Mark, Dworkin, Ronald, and Silvers, Robert B. (eds), The Legacy of Isaiah Berlin (New York: New York Review of Books, 2001), pp. 7390Google Scholar. See also Waldron, Jeremy, ‘Security and Liberty: The Image of Balance’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 11:2 (2003), pp. 191210CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Waldron, Jeremy, ‘Safety and Security’, Nebraska Law Review, 85:2 (2011), pp. 454507Google Scholar.

55 Dworkin, Ronald, Taking Rights Seriously (London: Duckworth, 1977)Google Scholar; Dworkin, Ronald, Sovereign Virtue (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000)Google Scholar; Griffin, James, On Human Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

56 Waldron, Jeremy, Liberal Rights: Collected Papers 1981–1991 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993)Google Scholar; Hunt, Lynn, Inventing Human Rights: A History (New York: W. W. Norton & Company, 2007)Google Scholar.

57 Cohen, G. A., ‘Facts and Principles’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 31:3 (2003), pp. 211–45CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Sangiovanni, Andrea, ‘Justice and the Priority of Politics to Morality’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 16:2 (2008), pp. 137–64CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Valentini, Laura, ‘Global Justice and Practice-Dependence: Conventionalism, Institutionalism, Functionalism’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 19:4 (2011), pp. 399418CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

58 Foot, Philippa, ‘Moral Arguments’, Mind, 67 (1958), pp. 502–13CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Foot, Philippa, ‘Moral Beliefs’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 59 (1958–9), pp. 83104CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

59 Rawls, ‘Kantian Constructivism’. See also Barry, Brian M., Justice as Impartiality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996)Google Scholar; O'Neill, Onora, Towards Justice and Virtue: A Constructive Account of Practical Reasoning (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; James, ‘Constructing Justice for Existing Practice’; Meckled-Garcia, Saladin, ‘On the Very Idea of Cosmopolitan Justice: Constructivism and International Agency’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 16:3 (2008), pp. 245–71CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

60 Rawls, ‘Kantian Constructivism’, p. 516.

61 Ibid., pp. 515–72.

62 James, ‘Constructing Justice for Existing Practice’, p. 282.

63 Jeffery, Renee, ‘Reason, Emotion, and the Problem of World Poverty: Moral Sentiment Theory and International Ethics’, International Theory, 3:1 (2011), p. 150CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

64 Price, Richard, ‘Moral Limit and Possibility in World Politics’, International Organization, 62:2 (2008), pp. 191220CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

65 Habermas, Jürgen, The Theory of Communicative Action, trans. McCarthy, Thomas, 2 vols (Cambridge: Polity, 1986)Google Scholar. See also Benhabib, Seyla, Situating the Self: Gender, Community and Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics (New York: Routledge, 1992)Google Scholar; Risse, ‘“Let's Argue!”’; Crawford, Neta, Argument and Change in World Politics: Ethics, Decolonization and Humanitarian Intervention (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kornprobst, Markus, ‘Argumentation and Compromise: Ireland's Selection of the Territorial Status Quo Norm’, International Organization, 61:1 (2007), pp. 6998CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

66 Plato, The Republic, trans. Lee, Desmond (London: Penguin, 1974)Google Scholar.

67 Rawls, ‘Two Concepts of Rules’; Oakeshott, On Human Conduct; Nardin, Law, Morality, and the Relations of States.

68 ICISS, The Responsibility to Protect: Report of the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty (Ottawa: International Development Research Centre, 2001)Google Scholar; see also Reus-Smit, Christian, ‘Human Rights and the Social Construction of Sovereignty’, Review of International Studies, 27:4 (2001), pp. 519–38CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

69 Rawls, Law of Peoples, pp. 78–81; Beitz, ‘Human Rights and the Law of Peoples’; Beitz, The Idea of Human Rights; Raz, ‘Human Rights Without Foundations’. See also Shue, Henry, Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980), pp. 2934Google Scholar; Donnelly, Jack, ‘Human Rights: A New Standard of Civilization?’, International Affairs, 74:1 (1998), pp. 123CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Donnelly, Jack, Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice (2nd edn, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2003), pp. 5770Google Scholar; Reus-Smit, ‘Human Rights and the Social Construction of Sovereignty’; Wheeler, Nicholas J., Saving Strangers: Humanitarian Intervention in International Society (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000)Google Scholar; Nickel, James W., Making Sense of Human Rights (2nd edn, Oxford: Blackwell, 2007), pp. 3841 and 70–91Google Scholar.

70 Pattison, James, ‘Outsourcing the Responsibility to Protect: Humanitarian Intervention and Private Military and Security Companies’, International Theory, 2:1 (2010), pp. 131CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Abrahamsen, Rita and Williams, Michael C., Security Beyond the State: Private Security in International Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011)Google Scholar.

71 Oakeshott, On Human Conduct; Nardin, Law, Morality, and the Relations of States; Karp, David Jason, ‘The Utopia and Reality of Sovereignty: Social Reality, Normative IR and “Organized Hypocrisy”’, Review of International Studies, 34:2 (2008), pp. 313–35CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

72 Rawls, Law of Peoples; Beitz, ‘Human Rights and the Law of Peoples’; Beitz, The Idea of Human Rights; Raz, ‘Human Rights Without Foundations’.

73 Arendt, Hannah, The Origins of Totalitarianism (New York: Harcourt, 1968), pp. 267302Google Scholar.

74 UNESCO (ed.), Human Rights: Comments and Interpretations.

75 O'Neill, Onora, ‘Agents of Justice’, Metaphilosophy, 32:1/2 (2001), pp. 184–5CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Sassen, Saskia, Authority, Territory, Rights: From Medieval to Global Assemblages (updated edn, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2006), pp. 277321Google Scholar; Hayden, Patrick, ‘From Exclusion to Containment: Arendt, Sovereign Power, and Statelessness’, Societies Without Borders, 3:2 (2008), pp. 248–69CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

76 Lauren, Paul Gordon, Power and Prejudice: Politics and Diplomacy of Racial Discrimination (Boulder: Westview Press, 1988), pp. 210–50Google Scholar; Simpson, A. W. Brian, Human Rights and the End of Empire: Britain and the Genesis of the European Convention (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001)Google Scholar.

77 Hobsbawm, Eric, The Age of Extremes: The Short Twentieth Century 1914–1991 (London: Michael Joseph, 1994)Google Scholar.

78 Weber, Max, ‘Politics as a Vocation’, in Gerth, H. H. and Mills, C. Wright (eds), From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology (New York: Oxford University Press, 1946), pp. 77128Google Scholar.

79 Donnelly, Universal Human Rights, pp. 57–70.

80 Ibid; Goodin, Robert E., ‘What is So Special about Our Fellow Countrymen?’, Ethics, 98:4 (1988), pp. 663–86CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Shue, Henry, ‘Mediating Duties’, Ethics, 98:4 (1988), pp. 687704CrossRefGoogle Scholar; O'Neill, ‘Agents of Justice’; Barry, Christian, ‘Global Justice: Aims, Arrangements, and Responsibilities’, in Erskine, Toni (ed.), Can Institutions Have Responsibilities? Collective Moral Agency and International Relations, (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003), pp. 230–31Google Scholar; Wenar, Leif, ‘Responsibility and Severe Poverty’, in Pogge, Thomas (ed.), Freedom from Poverty as a Human Right: Who Owes What to the Very Poor? (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), pp. 255–74Google Scholar.

81 Walzer, Michael, Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument with Historical Illustrations (New York: Basic Books, 1977)Google Scholar; Miller, David, On Nationality (Oxford: Clarendon, 1995)Google Scholar; Rawls, The Law of Peoples, pp. 38–9; Buchanan, Allen, ‘Rawls's Law of Peoples: Rules for a Vanished Westphalian World’, Ethics, 110:4 (2000), pp. 697721CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Pogge, Thomas, World Poverty and Human Rights (Cambridge: Polity, 2002), pp. 5963Google Scholar.

82 Karp, David Jason, Responsibility for Human Rights: Transnational Corporations, Principle and Practice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, forthcoming)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

83 Jackson, Quasi-States; Evans, Peter B., ‘The Eclipse of the State? Reflections on Stateness in an Era of Globalization’, World Politics, 50:1 (1997), pp. 6287CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Erskine, Toni, ‘Assigning Responsibilities to Institutional Moral Agents: The Case of States and Quasi-States’, in Erskine, Toni (ed.), Can Institutions Have Responsibilities?, pp. 1940Google Scholar.

84 Abrahamsen and Williams, Security Beyond the State: Private Security in International Politics. See also Clapham, Andrew, Human Rights in the Private Sphere (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993)Google Scholar; Clapham, Human Rights Obligations of Non-State Actors; Chesterman, Simon and Fisher, Angela (eds), Private Security, Public Order: The Outsourcing of Public Services and its Limits (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

85 Tilly, Charles, ‘War Making and State Making as Organized Crime’, in Evans, Peter B., Rueschemeyer, Dietrich, and Skocpol, Theda (eds), Bringing the State Back In (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), pp. 169–91CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Krause, Keith and Williams, Michael C., ‘From Strategy to Security: Foundations of Critical Security Studies’, in Krause, Keith and Williams, Michael C. (eds), Critical Security Studies: Concepts and Cases (London: Routledge, 1997), pp. 3359Google Scholar; Krahmann, Elke, ‘Security: Collective Good or Commodity?’, European Journal of International Relations, 14:3 (2008), pp. 379404CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

86 Cox, Robert, ‘States, Social Forces and World Orders’, Millennium, 10:2 (1981), pp. 126–55CrossRefGoogle Scholar.