Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-r5fsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T03:03:56.152Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Tough choices still

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 August 2015

TOMIS KAPITAN*
Affiliation:
Northern Illinois University, DeKalb, IL 60115, USA e-mail: [email protected]

Abstract

Some argue that an omniprescient being cannot choose between mutually exclusive actions none of which is known to be uniquely reasonable. The view assumes that faced with such a choice one must believe each alternative to be epistemically possible, thereby precluding foreknowledge of what one will do. E. J. Coffman (2011) has challenged this assumption, but I argue that not only does he fail to undermine it, there are independent reasons why choice – and intentional agency generally – entails a presumption of epistemic possibility. The apparent incompatibility between omniprescience and intentional agency continues to pose a tough choice for theists.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2015 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adolph, K. E. & Joh, A. (2009) ‘Multiple learning mechanism in the development of action’, in Woodward, A. & Needham, A. (eds) Learning and the Infant Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 172207.Google Scholar
Adolph, K. E. & Robinson, S. R. (2015) ‘Motor development’, in Liben, L. & Muller, U. (eds) Handbook of Child Psychology and Developmental Science, 7th edn., II (New York: Wiley), 114157.Google Scholar
Bratman, Michael (1987) Intentions, Plans, and Practical Reason (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Brener, J. & Mitchell, S. (1989) ‘Changes in energy expenditure and work during response acquisition in rats’, Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 15, 166175.Google Scholar
Coffman, E. J. (2011) ‘Omniprescience and tough choices’, Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion, 3, 4154.Google Scholar
Hofsten, von C. (2007) ‘Action in development’, Developmental Science, 10, 5460.Google Scholar
Hofsten, von C. (2012) ‘Action in infancy: a foundation for cognitive development’, in Prinz, W. (ed.) Action Science: The emergence of a new discipline (Cambridge MA: MIT), 255279.Google Scholar
Kapitan, Tomis (1986), ‘Deliberation and the presumption of open alternatives’, The Philosophical Quarterly, 36, 230251.Google Scholar
Kapitan, Tomis (1989) ‘Doxastic freedom: a compatibilist alternative’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 26, 3142.Google Scholar
Kapitan, Tomis (1991) ‘Agency and omniscience’, Religious Studies, 27, 105120.Google Scholar
Kapitan, Tomis (1994) ‘The incompatibility of omniscience and intentional action’, Religious Studies, 30, 5566.Google Scholar
Kapitan, Tomis (1997) ‘Acting and the open future: a brief rejoinder to David Hunt’, Religious Studies, 33, 287292.Google Scholar
Mele, Alfred (2003) Motivation and Agency (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Preston, J. & Wegner, D. (2009) ‘Elbow grease: when action feels like work’, in Morsella, E., Bargh, J. A., & Gollwitzer, P. M. (eds) Oxford Handbook of Human Action (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 569586.Google Scholar
Vohs, K. D. (2010) ‘Free will is costly: precious volitional resources’, in Baumeister, R. F., Mele, A., & Vohs, K. D. (eds) Free Will and Consciousness: How Might They Work? (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 6681.Google Scholar
Ziph, George K. (1949) Human Behavior and the Principle of Least Effort: An Introduction to Human Ecology (Cambridge MA: Addison-Wesley Press).Google Scholar