Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-20T05:36:32.810Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Theistic modal realism and causal modal collapse

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 July 2020

NUNO MAIA*
Affiliation:
Mansfield College, University of Oxford, Mansfield Road, Oxford, OX1 3TF, UK

Abstract

Theistic modal realism argues for an extension of Lewis's modal realism capable of accommodating a theistic God. By affording elegant solutions to many atheistic challenges, the view is of great theoretical utility for the theist. However, it has been objected that within a Lewisian framework God cannot be causally efficacious on pain of collapsing intuitively distinct modal notions. In this article I explain why these worries are ill-founded and show how God's existence and causal power over the pluriverse can be consistently understood. If successful, the proposal offers a congenial theistic way to adopt modal realism and address the atheological problems.

Type
Religious Studies Postgraduate Essay Prize
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Almeida, M. J. (2008) The Metaphysics of Perfect Beings (New York: Routledge).Google Scholar
Almeida, M. J. (2011) ‘Theistic modal realism?’, in Kvanvig, J. L. (ed.) Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion, III (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 115.Google Scholar
Almeida, M. J. (2017a) ‘Theistic modal realism I: the challenge of theistic actualism’, Philosophy Compass, 12, e12419, <https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12419>.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Almeida, M. J. (2017b) ‘Theistic modal realism II: theoretical benefits’, Philosophy Compass, 12, e12418, <https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12418>.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bricker, P. (1987) ‘Reducing possible worlds to language’, Philosophical Studies, 52, 331355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cameron, R. (2009) ‘God exists at every (modal realist) world: response to Sheehy’, Religious Studies, 45, 95100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collier, M. (2019) ‘God's necessity on Anselmian theistic genuine modal realism’, Sophia, 58, 331348.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Helm, P. (2010) Eternal God: A Study of God without Time, 2nd edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraay, J. K. (2011) ‘Theism and modal collapse’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 48, 361372.Google Scholar
Kretzmann, N. (1966) ‘Omniscience and immutability’, The Journal of Philosophy, 63, 409421.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leftow, B. (1991) Time and Eternity (New York: Cornell University Press).Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1968) ‘Counterpart theory and quantified modal logic’, The Journal of Philosophy, 65, 113126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1973) ‘Causation’, The Journal of Philosophy, 70, 556567.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1983a) ‘New work for a theory of universals’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61, 343377.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1983b) ‘Postscripts to ‘‘Counterpart theory and quantified modal logic’’ ’, in Philosophical Papers, I (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 4046.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1986) On the Plurality of Worlds (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Lewis, S. R. (2015) ‘Where (in logical space) is God?’, in Loewer, B. & Schaffer, J. (eds) A Companion to David Lewis (Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell), 206219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morris, T. & Menzel, C. (1986) ‘Absolute creation’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 23, 353362.Google Scholar
Nagasawa, Y. (2016) ‘Modal panentheism’, in Buckareff, A. & Nagasawa, Y. (eds) Alternative Concepts of God: Essays on the Metaphysics of the Divine (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 91105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, A. (1989) ‘Is Lewis's ‘genuine modal realism’ magical too?’, Mind, 98, 411421.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, J. (2004) ‘Causes need not be physically connected to their effects: The case for negative causation’, in Hitchcock, C. (ed.) Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Science (Oxford: Blackwell), 197216.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J. (2012) ‘Grounding, transitivity, and contrastivity’, in Correia, F. & Schnieder, B. (eds) Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 122138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, J. (2016) ‘The Metaphysics of Causation’, in Zalta, Edward (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2016 Edition), <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2016/entries/causation-metaphysics/>.Google Scholar
Sheehy, P. (2006) ‘Theism and modal realism’, Religious Studies, 42, 315328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sorabji, R. (1983) Time, Creation and the Continuum: Theories in Antiquity and the Early Middle Ages (London: Bloomsbury).Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. (1994) The Christian God (Oxford: Clarendon Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vance, C. (2016) ‘Classical theism and modal realism are incompatible’, Religious Studies, 52, 561572.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Inwagen, P. (2009) ‘God and other uncreated things’, in Timpe, K. (ed.) Metaphysics and God: Essays in Honor of Eleonore Stump (New York: Routledge), 320.Google Scholar
Wierenga, E. (1989) The Nature of God: An Inquiry into Divine Attributes (Ithaca: Cornell University Press).Google Scholar