Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-28T22:03:08.973Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Some Problems about Resurrection

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 October 2008

Philip L. Quinn
Affiliation:
Associate Professor of Philosophy, Brown University

Extract

Suppose that a person P1 dies some time during 1978. Many years later, the resurrection world, a perennial object of Christian concern, begins on the morning of the day of judgment. On its first morning there are in that world distinct persons, P2 and P3, each of whom is related in remarkably intimate ways to P1. You are to imagine that each of them satisfies each of the criteria or conditions necessary for identity with P1 to some extent, that both of them satisfy these conditions to exactly the same extent, and that every other denizen of the resurrection world satisfies each of these conditions to a lesser extent than P2 and P3 do. Thus, for example, philosophers often claim that bodily continuity is a necessary condition for personal identity. If it is, you might assume that the body P2 has on the morning of the day of judgment contains some of the same atoms the body of P11 contained when P1 died, and that P2's body on that day contains exactly n atoms from P1's body at the time of death just in case P3's body on that day contains exactly n atoms from P1's body at the time of death. Or, again, some philosophers hold that connectedness of memory is necessary for personal identity. If so, you are to suppose that on the morning of the day of judgment P3 seems to remember some of the events in the life of P1 having happened to him, and that P3 seems to remember a certain event in the life of P1 having happened to him just in case P2 seems to remember that very event in the life of P1 having happened to him. You are to fill in the details by adding complete parity between P2 and P3 with respect to similarity of DNA molecules, character traits and whatever else you deem relevant to personal identity. And, finally, you are to complete the story by imagining that P2 and P3 live very different sorts of lives in the resurrection world. To heighten the poignancy of the story, you might imagine that P2 enjoys forever after the beatitude promised to the blessed while P3 suffers the everlasting torments reserved for the damned.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1978

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 346 note 1 Penelhum, Terence, Survival and Disembodied Existence (Humanities Press: New York, 1970), p. 101.Google Scholar

page 347 note 1 Poincaré, Henri, The Foundations of Science (Science Press: Lancaster, 1946)Google Scholar; Reichenbach, Hans, The Philosophy of Space and Time (Dover: New York, 1957)Google Scholar; and Grünbaum, Adolf, Philosophical Problems of Space and Time, second edition (Reidel: Dordrecht, 1973).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

page 348 note 1 Descartes, René, Philosophical Works, 1, ed. Haldane, E. S. and Ross, G. R. T. (Dover: New York, 1955) p. 168. The quoted passage is from Meditations, III.Google Scholar

page 349 note 1 Edwards, Jonathan, Works, III, ed. Holbrook, C. A. (Yale University Press: New Haven, 1970), pp. 402–3. The quoted passage is from The Great Christian Doctrine of Original Sin Defended.Google Scholar

page 349 note 2 Ibid. p. 404.

page 352 note 1 Wiggins, David, ‘Locke, Butler and the Stream of Consciousness: and Men as a Natural Kind’, The Identities of Persons, ed. Rorty, A. O. (University of California Press: Berkeley, 1976) p. 157.Google Scholar

page 353 note 1 Lewis, David, ‘Survival and Identity’, The Identities of Persons, ed. Rorty, A. O. (University of California Press: Berkeley, 1976), pp. 22–9.Google Scholar

page 355 note 1 Shoemaker, Sydney, Self-Knowledge and Self-Identity (Cornell University Press: Ithaca, 1963), pp. 214–15 and 254–5.Google Scholar

page 355 note 2 Butler, Joseph, ‘Of Personal Identity’, Body, Mind and Death, ed. Flew, A. (Macmillan: New York, 1964).Google Scholar

page 355 note 3 Mavrodes, George, ‘The Life Everlasting and the Bodily Criterion of Identity’, Nous, 11 (1977) 2739.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

page 356 note 1 Chisholm, Roderick, ‘Reply to Strawson's Comments’, Language, Belief and Metaphysics, ed. Kiefer, H. E. and Munitz, M. K. (State University of New York Press: Albany, 1970), p. 188.Google Scholar

page 357 note 1 Royce, Josiah, The Conception of Immortality (Houghton, Mifflin and Company: Boston, 1900), p. 14.Google Scholar

page 357 note 2 Descartes, René, ‘Letter to Mesland, 9 February 1645’, Philosophical Letters, ed. Kenny, A. (Clarendon Press: Oxford, 1970), p. 157.Google Scholar

page 358 note 1 Descartes, René, ‘Letter to Regius, January 1642’, Philosophical Letters, ed. Kenny, A. (Clarendon Press: Oxford, 1970), p. 130.Google Scholar

page 358 note 2 Geach, Peter, God and the Soul (Schocken: New York, 1969), p. 22.Google Scholar

page 358 note 3 Royce, Josiah, op. cit. p. 71.Google Scholar

page 359 note 1 I read an earlier version of this paper at Denison University in March, 1978. I thank members of my audience there for discussion which helped me in making revisions.Google Scholar