Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-t5tsf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T19:52:57.022Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Simple Trinitarianism and empty names

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 May 2018

SHIEVA KLEINSCHMIDT*
Affiliation:
University of Southern California, 3709 Trousdale Pkwy, Los Angeles, CA 90089, USA

Abstract

According to Simple Trinitarianism, God is mereologically simple, and the Father, Son, and Holy Spirit are not identified with any entities in our ontology. Thus the Simple Trinitarian is able to avoid conflating Persons or multiplying Gods, and does not have to identify the Persons with minor entities or entities partly disjoint from God. However, to maintain that Trinitarian sentences are nonetheless true, the Simple Trinitarian will need a non-standard semantics. I explore one option for this, involving taking ‘the Father’, ‘the Son’, and ‘the Holy Spirit’ to be empty names. By adopting a positive, Free Logic, we can take these names to make semantic contributions and play roles in true sentences, while blocking problematic inferences.

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aquinas, Thomas (1259–1265) Summa Contra Gentiles: Book Four: Salvation, O'Neil, C. J. (tr.) (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1957).Google Scholar
Aquinas, Thomas (1266–1268) Summa Theologica, Fathers of the English Dominican Province (trs) (London: Oates and Washburne, 1920).Google Scholar
Bacon, Andrew (2013) ‘Quantificational logic and empty names’, Philosopher's Imprint, 13, 121.Google Scholar
Barth, Karl (1956) Church Dogmatics, I: The Doctrine of the Word of God (Prolegomena to Church Dogmatics, Being Vol. I, 2), Thomson, G. T., Knight, H., Bromiley, G. W., & Torrance, T. F. (eds & trs), (Edinburgh: T. and T. Clark).Google Scholar
Burge, Tyler (1974) ‘Truth and singular terms’, Nous, 8, 309325.Google Scholar
Horgan, Terry, & Potrč, Matjaž (2000) ‘Blobjectivism and indirect correspondence’, Facta Philosophica, 2, 249270.Google Scholar
Howard-Snyder, Dan (2003) ‘Trinity monotheism’, Philosophia Christi, 5, 375403.Google Scholar
Howard-Snyder, Dan (2015) ‘Trinity’, Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Online, <http://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/trinity/v-2>..>Google Scholar
Kleinschmidt, Shieva (2016) ‘Simple trinitarianism and feature-placing sentences’, Faith and Philosophy, 33, 257277.Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul (1963) ‘Semantical considerations on modal logic’, Acta Philosophica Fennica, 16, 8394.Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul (1973) Reference and Existence: The John Locke Lectures for 1973 (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Lambert, Karel (1963) ‘Existential import revisited’, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 4, 288–262.Google Scholar
Moreland, J. P., & Craig, W. L. (2003) Philosophical Foundations for a Christian Worldview (Downers Grove IL: InterVarsity Press).Google Scholar
Pickup, Martin (forthcoming) ‘The Trinity and extended simples’, Faith and Philosophy.Google Scholar
Rahner, Karl (1997) The Trinity, Donceel, Joseph (tr.) (New York: Crossroad Publishing Co.).Google Scholar
Salmon, Nathan (1998) ‘Nonexistence’, Nous, 32, 277319.Google Scholar
Sainsbury, R. M. (2005) Reference without Referents (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Swinburne, Richard (1994) The Christian God (New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Tuggy, Dale (2013) ‘Trinity’, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, <http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/trinity/>..>Google Scholar