Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dlnhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T02:56:46.825Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Indirect epistemic reasons and religious belief

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 July 2016

KIRK LOUGHEED*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, McMaster University, Hamilton, Ontario, L8S4L8, Canada
ROBERT MARK SIMPSON*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Monash University, Victoria, 3800, Australia

Abstract

If believing P will result in epistemically good outcomes, does this generate an epistemic reason to believe P, or just a pragmatic reason? Conceiving of such reasons as epistemic reasons seems to lead to absurdity, e.g. by allowing that someone can rationally hold beliefs that conflict with her assessment of her evidence's probative force. We explain how this and other intuitively unwelcome results can be avoided. We also suggest a positive case for conceiving of such reasons as epistemic reasons, namely, that they exhibit a form of interpersonal normative parity that's typical of epistemic reasons but not pragmatic reasons. We then link this discussion to religious belief, suggesting that there are sometimes indirect epistemic reasons for religious belief, and that certain characterizations of religious belief are instructive in thinking about how to take account of indirect epistemic reasons.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adler, J. E. (2002) Belief's Own Ethics (Cambridge MA: MIT Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ahlstrom-Vij, K. & Dunn, J. (2014) ‘A defence of epistemic consequentialism’, The Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 541551.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alston, W. (1991) Perceiving God (Ithaca: Cornell University Press).Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957) Intention (Oxford: Basil Blackwell).Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1958) ‘Modern moral philosophy’, Philosophy, 33, 119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berker, S. (2013) ‘Epistemic teleology and the separateness of propositions’, Philosophical Review, 122, 337393.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bourget, D. & Chalmers, D. (2014) ‘What do philosophers believe?’, Philosophical Studies, 170, 465500.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christensen, D. (2007) ‘Epistemology of disagreement: the good news’, Philosophical Review, 116, 187217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clifford, W. K. (1876) ‘The ethics of belief’, The Contemporary Review, 29, 289309.Google Scholar
Conee, E. (2009) ‘Peerage’, Episteme, 6, 313323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
David, M. (2014) ‘Truth as the primary epistemic goal: a working hypothesis’, in Steup, M., Turri, J., & Sosa, E. (eds) Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, 2nd edn (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell), 363377.Google Scholar
Darwall, S. (2006) The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Duarte, J. L., Crawford, J. T., Stern, C., Haidt, J., Jussim, L., & Tetlock, P. E. (forthcoming) ‘Political diversity will improve social psychological science’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences.Google Scholar
Elga, A. (2007) ‘Reflection and disagreement’, Noûs, 41, 478502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elgin, C. Z. (2010) ‘Persistent disagreement’, in Feldman, R. & Warfield, T. A. (eds) Disagreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 5368.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feldman, R. (2011) ‘Reasonable religious disagreements’, in Goldman, A. I. & Whitcomb, D. (eds) Social Epistemology: Essential Readings (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 137157.Google Scholar
Firth, R. (1981) ‘Epistemic merit: intrinsic and instrumental’, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 55, 523.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fumerton, R. (2001) ‘Epistemic justification and normativity’, in Steup, M. (ed.) Knowledge, Truth, and Duty: Essays on Epistemic Justification, Responsibility, and Virtue (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 4960.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greaves, H. (2013) ‘Epistemic decision theory’, Mind, 122, 915952.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howard-Snyder, F. (1993) ‘Rule consequentialism is a rubber duck’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 30, 271278.Google Scholar
James, W. (1912) The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy (London: Longmans, Green, and Co.).Google Scholar
Jordan, J. (2014) ‘Pragmatic arguments and belief in God’, in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition), <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/pragmatic-belief-god/>.Google Scholar
Kelly, T. (2003) ‘Epistemic rationality as instrumental rationality: a critique’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66, 612640.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelly, T. (2014) ‘Evidence can be permissive’, in Steup, M., Turri, J., & Sosa, E. (eds) Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, 2nd edn (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell), 298311.Google Scholar
Kopec, M. & Titelbaum, M. (forthcoming) ‘The uniqueness thesis’, Philosophy Compass.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1993) The Advancement of Science (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Matheson, J. (2015) The Epistemic Significance of Disagreement (New York: Palgrave Macmillan).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, J. S. (1859) On Liberty (London: J. W. Parker & Son).Google Scholar
Moffett, M. (2007) ‘Reasonable disagreement and rational group inquiry’, Episteme, 4, 352367.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, T. (1986) The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Owens, D. (2003) ‘Does belief have an aim?’, Philosophical Studies, 115, 283305.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pascal, B. (1950) Pascal's Pensées (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul).Google Scholar
Percival, P. (2002) ‘Epistemic consequentialism’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 76, 121151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plantinga, A. (1984) ‘Advice to Christian philosophers’, Faith and Philosophy, 1, 253271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plantinga, A. (1993) Warrant and Proper Function (New York: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plantinga, A. (2000) Warranted Christian Belief (New York: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rinard, S. (forthcoming) ‘No exception for belief’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.Google Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. (1956) ‘Extreme and restricted utilitarianism’, The Philosophical Quarterly, 6, 344354.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stanley, J. (2005) Knowledge and Practical Interests (New York: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Talbot, B. (2014) ‘Truth promoting non-evidential reasons for belief’, Philosophical Studies, 168, 599618.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, R. (2005) ‘Epistemic permissiveness’, Philosophical Perspectives, 19, 445459.CrossRefGoogle Scholar