Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-r5fsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T00:58:17.905Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Factual Reference of Theological Assertions

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 October 2008

Paul R. Clifford
Affiliation:
President, Selly Oak Colleges

Extract

Professor Kai Nielsen is one of the most forceful proponents of the view that theological assertions have no factual reference because they are compatible with any empirical state of affairs; no evidence, it is alleged, is allowed to count as falsification of such assertions, and therefore they spuriously purport to be what they are not. In this he follows the well-known essay by Professor Antony Flew in which the same argument was advanced, and Nielsen's own most recent contribution on the subject in Religious Studies should be read against the background of his earlier controversy with Professors John Hick and George Mavrodes in The Canadian Journal of Theology. In this latest article he broadens the canvas to question the significance of applying language and concepts appropriate to the realm of empirical observation to anything that is held to transcend it; and this is the substance of Part II of his paper, in which he engages in debate with Professor Ian Crombie, treading well-worn ground that has been the subject of innumerable philosophical discussions. The rest of the paper, however, is a restatement of his earlier contention, and it is with this more limited issue that I shall be concerned in what follows. For I believe that Nielsen is wrong in two quite fundamental respects: (1) he is mistaken in supposing that theological assertions are compatible with any empirical state of affairs: (2) he bases his critique of theological assertions on a far too uncritical appraisal of the principles of verification and falsification in the case of ordinary factual statements. If I am right, the larger questions raised in Part II will still remain open, but it is high time that the ‘verification-falsification argument’ should be shown to be unfounded.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1967

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 339 note 1 Flew, Antony, ‘Theology and Falsification’, New Essays in Philosophical Theology (LondonS.C.M., 1955), pp. 9699.Google Scholar

page 339 note 2 Religious Studies, vol. II, no. 1 (1966), pp. 13–36.

page 339 note 3 Hick, John, ‘Theology and Verification’, Theology Today, XVII (1960), pp. 1231CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Nielsen, Kai, ‘Eschatological Verification’, Canadian Journal of Theology, IX (1963), pp. 271281Google Scholar; Mavrodes, George I., ‘God and Verification’, Canadian Journal of Theology, X (1964), pp. 187191Google Scholar; Nielsen, Kai, ‘God and Verification Again’, Canadian Journal of Theology, XI (1965), pp. 135141.Google Scholar

page 340 note 1 ‘On Fixing the Reference Range of God’, Religious Studies, vol. 11, no. 1 (1966), p. 16.

page 343 note 1 Hare maintains that the descriptive meaning of such words as ‘good’ is ‘secondary to their evaluative meaning’. Cf. The Language of Morals (Oxford. Clarendon, 1952), p. 118.

page 343 note 2 Nowell-Smith, P. H., Ethics (Harmondsworth. Penguin, 1954).Google Scholar

page 344 note 1 Braithwaite, R. B., An Empiricist's View of the Mature of Religious Belief, Eddington Memorial Lecture (C.U.P., 1955).Google Scholar

page 344 note 2 Ps. 91: 7.

page 345 note 1 Clifford, P. R., ‘Omnipotence and the Problem of Evil’, Journal of Religion, XLI (1961), pp. 118128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar