Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-g7gxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T12:26:25.352Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Singular Causation and Law

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2023

Gürol Irzik*
Affiliation:
Bogaziçi University
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

Humean accounts of law are at the same time accounts of causation. Accordingly, since laws of nature are nothing but contingent cosmic regularities, to be a cause is just to be an instance of such a law. It follows from this view that it is logically impossible that there be causally related events which are not law-governed. Any particular cause-effect pair instantiates some law of nature, where the law is understood as a regularity. The regularity itself may be understood phenomenalistically, that is, as holding between sense impressions, or realistically, that is, as holding between objective events or event-types. These days even empiricists are realists to some extent, so I will eschew the radically empiricist version and assume that when a Humean talks about regularities, he is referring to objective events, states or processes in nature, not to his subjective experiences.

Type
Part IX. Belief, Cause and Induction
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1990

Footnotes

1

I wish to thank Arda Denkel for his helpful comments on an earlier version of this paper.

References

Armstrong, D.M. (1983), What is a Law of Nature? Cambridge: Cambridge University press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blau, P.M. and Duncan, O.D. (1967), The American Occupational Structure. New York: John Wiley and Sons, Inc.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. (1983), How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. (1967), “Causal Relations”, The Journal of Philosophy 64: 691703.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. (1968), “Actions, Reasons, and Causes”, in The Philosophy of Action, White, A. (ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 7994.Google Scholar
Glymour, C. (1983), “Social Science and Social Physics”, Behavioral Science 28: 126134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glymour, C. et al. (1987), Discovering Causal Structure. Orlando: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, C.G. (1970), Aspects of Scientific Explanation. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Kim, J. (1973), “Causation, Nomic Subsumption, and the Concept of Event”, The Journal of Philosophy LXX: 217236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Margenau, H. and van Fraassen, B. (1968), “Causality”, in Contemporary Philosophy, Volume 2, Klibansky, R. (ed.), Florence: La Nova Italia Editrice, pp. 319328.Google Scholar
Salmon, W. C. (1984), Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar