Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-g7gxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T03:25:34.482Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Informal Aspects of Theory Reduction

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

David L. Hull*
Affiliation:
The University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee

Extract

The issues which separate the members of this symposium concern the nature of reduction and scientific theories. However, these issues involve primarily informal aspects of theory reduction. But more than this, they concern the nature of philosophy of science itself.

Kenneth Schaffner (1967) has set out what he terms a general reduction paradigm, a development of earlier efforts by such philosophers as Ernest Nagel, J. H. Woodger, and Carl Hempel. This model, according to Schaffner, “represents an ideal standard for accomplished reductions, and does not characterize the research programmes of molecular biologists.” Following the lead of his predecessors, Schaffner does not intend for his model of theory reduction to characterize the ongoing process of science (Wimsatt’s rational) but an abstract, formal relation between atemporal rational reconstructions of scientific theories (Wimsatt’s rational).

Type
Symposium: History and Philosophy of Biology
Copyright
Copyright © 1976 by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht-Holland

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bibiliography

Causey, R. L.: 1972, ‘Uniform Microreductions’, Synthese 25, 176218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fleming, Donald (ed.): 1964, The Mechanistic Conception of Life, The Belknap Press, Cambridge, Mass.Google Scholar
Hull, D. L.: 1972, ‘Reduction in Genetics – Biology or Philosophy?’, Philosophy of Science 39,491499.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, D. L.: 1973, ‘Reduction in Genetics – Doing the Impossible,’ in Suppes, P. (ed.), Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, vol. IV, North-Holland Publishing Co., pp. 619635.Google Scholar
Hull, D. L.: 1974, Philosophy of the Biological Sciences, Prentice-Hall, Inc. Englewood Cliffs.Google Scholar
Knight, David M.: 1967, Atoms and Elements, Hutchinson University Library, London.Google Scholar
Kyburg, H.: 1968, Philosophy of Science, Macmillan, New York.Google Scholar
Lakatos, I.: 1971, ‘History of Science and Its Rational Reconstruction,’ Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 8, 91136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruse, Michael: 1971, ‘Reduction, Replacement and Molecular Biology,’ Dialectica 25, 3972.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruse, Michael: 1973, The Philosophy of Biology, Hutchinson University Library, London.Google Scholar
Schaffner, Kenneth: 1967, ‘Approaches to Reduction,’ Philosophy of Science 34, 137147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffner, Kenneth: 1969, ‘The Watson-Crick Model and Reductionism,’ The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 20,325348.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simon, Michael: 1971, The Matter of Life, Yale University Press, New Haven.Google Scholar
Woodger, J.: 1937, The Axiomatic Method in Biology, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar