Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-fbnjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T17:13:46.502Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Implications of Incommensurability

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Philip Kitcher*
Affiliation:
University of Vermont

Extract

In 1962, Thomas Kuhn offered an account of the difficulties which attend the reception of revolutionary scientific ideas: “Communication across the revolutionary divide,” he wrote, “is inevitably partial.” (Kuhn 1962, p. 149). Eight years later, in the postscript to the second edition of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, he sounded the same theme, characterizing the participants in revolutionary debates as people who attach their terms to nature differently, so that their communication is “inevitably only partial” (Kuhn 1970, p. 198). In his most recent discussion of these issues (Kuhn 1983), Kuhn has explained more clearly than before the nature of the differences in language which he takes to be present in revolutionary debates.

Type
Part XVI. Commensurability, Comparability, Communicability
Copyright
Copyright © 1983 Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Cavendish, H. (1784-85). “Experiments on Air”. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London LXXIV, LXXV: 119-153, 372-384. (As reprinted as Experiments on Air (Alembic Club Reprints, no. 3.) Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1902.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. and Harman, G. (eds.). (1972). Semantics of Natural Language. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donnellan, K. (1970). “Proper Names and Identifying Descriptions.” Synthese 21: 335-358. (As reprinted in Davidson and Harman (1972). Pages 356-379.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Earman, J. and Fine, A. (1977). “Against Indeterminacy.” Journal of Philosophy 74: 535-538.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Field, H. (1973). “Theory Change and the Indeterminacy of Reference.” Journal of Philosophy 70: 462-481.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, P.S. (1978). “Theories, Theorists and Theoretical Change.” Philosophical Review 87: 519-547.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, P.S. (1982). “Genes.” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 33: 337-359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, S. (1972). “Naming and Necessity.” In Davidson and Harman (1972). Pages 253-355. (Also reprinted as a book, Cambridge: Harvard University Press (1980).Google Scholar
Kuhn, T.S. (1962). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T.S. (1970). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T.S. (1977). “Objectivity, Value Judgment, and Theory Choice.” In Kuhn, T.S., The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Pages 320-339.10.7208/chicago/9780226217239.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, T.S. (1983). “Commensurability, Comparability, Communicability.” In PSA 1982 Volume 2. Edited by Asquith, P.D. and Nickles, T.. East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association. Pages 669-688.Google Scholar
Lakatos, I. (1978). Philosophical Papers. Volume I. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its Problems. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Lavoisier, A. (1777). Réflexions sur Phlogistlque. In Oeuvres, Volume 2. New York: Johnson Reprint Company.Google Scholar
Lewis, D.K. (1970). “How to Define Theoretical Terms.” Journal of Philosophy 67: 1)27-41)6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. (1975). Philosophical Papers, Volume 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar