Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T15:10:34.334Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Comments on Maddy and Tymoczko

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Pau Benacerraf*
Affiliation:
Princeton University

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Part XI. New Directions in the Philosophy of Mathematics
Copyright
Copyright © 1985 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

Comments on (Maddy 1985) and (Tymoczko 1985), constituting, along with comments by George Boolos, a Symposium entitled “New Directions in the Philosophy of Mathematics”, Philosophy of Science Association Meetings, Chicago, October 1984. I am grateful to Paul Boghossian for a number of discussions of Kripke's Wittgenstein. He is blameless for the remarks I make here.

References

Asquith, Peter D and Kitcher, Phili, (eds.). (1985). PSA 1984, Volume 2. East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
Benacerraf, Paul (1973). “Mathematical Truth.” Journal of Philosophy 70: 661-680. (As reprinted in Benacerraf and Putnam (1983). Pages 403-120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benacerraf, Paul and Putnam, Hilar, (eds.). (1983). Philosophy of Mathematics Selected Readings. 2nd ed. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Benacerraf, Paul (1985). “Skolem and the Skeptic.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume LIX: 85-115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
GÖdel, Kur. (1947/64). “What is Cantor's Continuum Problem.” American Mathematical Monthly 54: 515-525. (As reprinted in Benacerraf and Putnam (1983). Pages 470-485.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hallett, Michael (1984). Cantorian Set Theory and Limitation of Size. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kreisel, Georg (1965). “Informal Rigour and Completeness Proofs.” In Problems in the Philosophy of Mathematics. (Proceedings of the International Colloquium in the Philosophy of Science. London, 1965, Volume 1.) Edited by Imre Lakatos. Amsterdam: North Holland. Pages 138-171.Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul A (1982). Wittgenstein on Rules and the Private Language Argument. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Maddy, Penelope (1985). “New Directions in the Philosophy of Mathematics.” In Asquith and Kitcher (1985). Pages 427-448.Google Scholar
Scott, Dana (1974). “Axiomatizing Set Theory.” In Axiomatic Set Theory. (Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics. Volume 13, Part II.) Edited by T.J. Jech. Providence: American Mathematical Society. Pages 207-214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tymoczko, Thomas (1985). “GÖdel, Wittgenstein, and the Nature of Mathematical Knowledge.” In Asquith and Kitcher (1985). Pages 449-468.Google Scholar
van Aken, Jame (Forthcoming). “Axioms for the Set Theoretic Hierarchy.” Journal of Philosophiocal Logic.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1953). Philosophical Investigations, (trans.) Anscombe, G.E.M. New York: MacMillan.Google Scholar