Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-v9fdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-16T15:30:30.441Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Ambiguous Role of Experience in Cartesian Science

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Desmond M. Clarke*
Affiliation:
University College, Cork, Ireland

Extract

There is something methodologically amiss in Cartesian science. Apart from some recent commentators ([1], [12], [13]), the source of Descartes’ problems is usually located in a Rationalist preference for the evidentiary force of “reason” rather than “experience” in the construction and testing of scientific hypotheses. In other words, Descartes’ metaphysics and theory of knowledge are said to imply a scientific methodology which precludes, or greatly diminishes, the decisive role of empirical evidence in the development of a viable science of nature ([2]; [14], p. 384-5; [15]. P. 15; [16]).

I wish to agree in general with the recognition of some kind of miscarriage in Descartes’ methodology, but I locate the source of his scientific weakness elsewhere. I argue that there is no unusual or especially significant opposition between reason and experience in Cartesian methodology - nor do Descartes’ problems derive primarily from his. metaphysics.

Type
Part V. Epistemological Foundations of Science
Copyright
Copyright © 1976 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Buchdahl, Gerd. “The Relevance of Descartes’ Philosophy for Modern Philosophy of Science.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 1 (1963): 227-49.Google Scholar
Chauvois, Louis. Descartes; Sa Méthode et ses erreurs en Physiologie. Paris: Les Editions de Clère, 1966.Google Scholar
Clarke, Desmond M. “The Concept of Experience in Descartes’ Theory of Knowledge.” Forthcoming in Studia Leibnitiana, 1976.Google Scholar
Clarke, Desmond M. “Innate Ideas: Descartes and Chomsky.” Forthcoming in Philosophical Studies (Ireland), 1976.Google Scholar
Clarke, Desmond M. “Descartes’ Use of ‘Demonstration’ and ‘Deduction'.” Forthcoming in The Modern Schoolman, 1977.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke, Desmond M. “The Impact Rules of Descartes’ Physics.” Forthcoming in Isis, 1976.Google Scholar
Cotgrave, Randle, A Dictionarie of the French and English Tongues. London: Islip, 1632. (Reproduced by University Microfilms Library Service, Ann Arbor, Michigan.)Google Scholar
Descartes, René. Oeuvres. Edited by Adam, C. and Tannery, P.. New Edition. Paris: Vrin, 1964 - .Google Scholar
Descartes, René. Correspondance. Edited by C. Adam and G. Milhaud. 8 Volumes. Paris: Volume I, II, Alcan; Volumes III-VIII, Presses Universitaires de France, 1936-63.Google Scholar
Duhem, Pierre. The Aim and Structure of Physical Science. Translated by Philip P. Wiener. New York: Atheneum, 1962.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul K. Against Method. London: NLB, 1975.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry. Demons. Dreamers, and Madmen. Indianapolis and New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1970.Google Scholar
Laudan, Laurens. “The Clock Metaphor and Probabilism: The Impact of Descartes on English Methodological Thought, 1650-65 .” Annals of Science 22 (1966): 73-104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Randall, John Herman Jr. The Career of Philosophy. New York and London: Columbia University Press, 1962.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rodis-Lewis, Geneviève. Descartes et le rationalisme. (2nd ed.). Paris:Presses Universitaires de France, 1970.Google Scholar
Schouls, Peter A. “Reason, Method and Science in the Philosphy of Descartes.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 50 (1972): 30-39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar