Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-fbnjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T15:10:49.617Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Causal Decision Theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Eller Eells*
Affiliation:
University of Wisconsin-Madison

Extract

Philosophers concerned with the nature of rational decision making have distinguished two paradigms for rational deliberation. According to evidential decision theory, one, should, when faced with alternative courses of action, perform an act whose performance would constitute the best possible evidence that one will, get the good outcomes and not get the bad outcomes. On this paradigm, therefore, deliberation consists in trying to figure out which of the available actions is such that performing it should cause one's beliefs to be altered in such a way that the good outcomes will be as subjectively probable as possible and the bad outcomes as subjectively improbable aspossible, given the constraints imposed by one's prior beliefs. According to causal decision theory, on the-other hand, one should be explicitly concerned with the causal relations between the available acts and the possible outcomes.

Type
Part IV. Causal Decision Theory
Copyright
Copyright © 1985 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

I thank the university of wisconsin-Madison graduate School for financial support, and Elliott Sober for useful comments an an earlier draft.

References

Campbell, R and Sowden, L (eds.). (1985). Paradoxes of Rationality and Cooperation: Prisoner's Dilemma and Hewcomb's Problem. Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press.Google Scholar
Cartwrlght, N (1979). “Causal Laws and Effective Strategies.” Nous 13: 119-437.Google Scholar
Eells, E (1980). Newcomb's Paradox and the Prinoiple of Maximizing Conditional Expected Utility. Unpublished Ph.D. Dissertation, University of California, Berkeley. University Microfilms Publication Number ADG80-29383.Google Scholar
Eells, E (1982). Rational Deoislon and Causality. Cambridge, England, and New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eells, E and Sober, E (1983). “Probabilistic Causality and the Question of Transitivity.” Philosophy of Science 50: 35-57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eells, E (1984). “Common Causes and Decision Theory.” Unpublished manuscript, University of Wisconsin-Madison.Google Scholar
Eells, E (1984a). “Newcomb's Many Solutions.” Theory and Decision 16: 59-105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eells, E (1984b). “Metatiokles and the Dynamics of Deliberation.” Theory and Decision 17: 71-95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eells, E (1985). “Reply to Jackson and Pargetter.” In Campbell and Sowden (1985). Pages 219-223.Google Scholar
Garber, D (1983). “Old Evidence and Logical Omniscience in Bayesian Confirmation Theory.” In Testing Scientific Theories. Edited by Earman, J. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Pages 99-131.Google Scholar
Gibbard, A and Harper, W (1978). “Counterfactuals and Two Kinds of Expected Utility.” In Foundations and Applications of Decision Theory, Volume 1. (The University of Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science. Volume 13.) Edited by C.A. Hooker, J.J. Leach, and E.F. MoClennen. Dordrecht: Reidel. Pages 125-162. (As reprinted in Ifs. (The University of Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, Volume 15.) Edited by W. Harper, R. Stalnaker, and G. Pearce. Dordrecht: Reidel, 1981. Pages 153-190. Also reprinted i n Campbell and Sowden (1985). Pages 133-158.)Google Scholar
Hacking, I (1967). “Slightly More Realistic Personal Probability.” Philosophy of Science 34: 311-325.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horwich, P (1983). “Decision Theory in the Light of Newcomb's Problem.” Unpublished manuscript, MIT.Google Scholar
Jackson, F and Pargetter, R (1983). “Where the Tickle Defense Goes Wrong.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61: 295-299.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, F (1985). “Where the Tickle Defense Goes Wrong.” Reprinting of Jackson and Pargetter (1983), with postscript (on what I have called the “metatickle defense”). In Campbell and Sowden (1985). Pages 211-219.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, R.C (1965). The Logic of Decision. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, R.C (1981). “The Logic of Decision Defended.” Synthese 18: 473-492.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jeffrey, R.C (1983). The Logic of Decision. 2nd ed. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kyburg, H.E Jr., (1974). The Logical Foundations of Statistical Inference. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kyburg, H.E Jr., (1980). “Acts and Conditional Probabilities.” Theory and Decision 12: 149-171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D (1981). “Causal Decision Theory.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 59: 5-30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reichenbach, H (1956). The Direction of Time. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, W (1978). “Why Ask ‘Why?’? — An Inquiry Concerning Scientific Explanation.” Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 51: 683-705.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skyrms, B (1980). Causal necessity: A Pragmatic Investigation of the Necessity of Laws. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Skyrms, B (1982). “Causal Decision Theory.” Journal of Philosophy 79: 695-711.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skyrms, B (1984). Pragmatics and Empiricism. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.Google Scholar