Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T18:29:55.811Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Political Realism: An Essay on the Politics of Value Conflict

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2023

Paul M. Sniderman*
Affiliation:
Stanford University, USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

The Ithiel de Sola Pool Award is for work throughout my career—work that I have done with many and with the help of so many more. I thank the committee for this honor and, with it, the opportunity to honor another: Merrill Shanks.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the American Political Science Association

DEDICATION

The Ithiel de Sola Pool Award is for work throughout my career—work that I have done with many and with the help of so many more. I thank the committee for this honor and, with it, the opportunity to honor another: Merrill Shanks.

I will be in his debt always—as are so many others. The introduction of computer-assisted randomized experiments is arguably the most important methodological innovation in public opinion research in many years. Merrill was the creator of Computer-Assisted Survey Execution System (CASES), which made possible the introduction of computer-assisted randomized experiments.

Before CASES, randomized experiments could be done in public opinion studies only in a so-called split-ballot form: modally one variation of one factor. A more procrustean design is difficult to imagine. With CASES, questionnaires became computer programs and the wording, formatting, and order of questions are varied at random, effortlessly for an interviewer, invisibly to those being interviewed. There are statistical limits on the design of survey experiments, but in large-scale surveys, the main constraint now is the investigator’s imagination.

CASES is a unified data-collection system. It is an extraordinary technical achievement, snapped up by many organizations including the US Census Bureau and the US Department of Labor Statistics. Merrill also is responsible for developing Survey Documentation and Analysis (SDA), a sister application of CASES. No license is required, unlike Stata and SPSS. Anyone can access the SDA website (sda.berkeley.edu) and other data archives maintained by organizations, such as the Inter-University Consortium for Political and Social Research and the Integrated Public Use Microdata Series, and analyze hundreds of datasets, including the flagship General Social Survey for sociology and the American National Elections Study for political science. A great many make use of the SDA website—in 2021, approximately a half-million times, including myriad students taking classes at universities, colleges, and junior colleges, all for free. SDA democratized data analysis—a singular contribution.Footnote 1 Hence, the dedication of this Ithiel de Sola Pool lecture in honor of Merrill Shanks.

My aim is to be a spokesperson for an idea: political realism.Footnote 2 The root intuition is that to understand the choices that citizens make, the starting point should be the circumstances in politics to which they are responding. This may seem self-evident. Would that it were, for what I show is that political scientists in the same line of work as I am, have gotten caught up in analyzing the psychology of politics at the expense of politics.

My aim is to be a spokesperson for an idea: political realism. The root intuition is that to understand the choices that citizens make, the starting point should be the circumstances in politics to which they are responding. This may seem self-evident. Would that it were, for what I show is that political scientists in the same line of work as I am, have gotten caught up in analyzing the psychology of politics at the expense of politics.

What work is “realism” in political realism doing? My guide is G. H. Hardy. Mathematics is so, Hardy declared, “not because we think so, or because our minds are shaped in one way rather than another, but because it is so, because reality is built that way” (1940, 130; italics in original). I make the same claim for politics twice. Liberals who respond to the Democratic Party as the party of liberalism on civil liberties and conservatives who respond to the Republican Party as the party of conservatism are not engaging in motivated reasoning. Neither are liberals who believe that traditional Muslim values regarding the rights and responsibilities of women conflict with liberal values. On the contrary, in these quite different circumstances, liberals respond as they do “because [political] reality is built that way” (Hardy Reference Hardy1940, 130). Reality bites—that is my claim. I begin with a motivating example: the “Big Sort.”

A MOTIVATING EXAMPLE

American party politics is intensely polarized, all agree. Republicans fear and loathe Democrats, Democrats fear and loathe Republicans, if not more than ever before—at any rate, far more so than 30 years ago (Iyengar, Sood, and Lelkes Reference Iyengar, Sood and Lelkes2012; Iyengar and Westwood Reference Iyengar and Westwood2014). A small library of studies reports that political feelings spill over into their personal lives—who they have as friends, prefer to date, and would like their children to marry and what they elect to listen to and read.Footnote 3 If Democrats like to live their lives with Democrats and Republicans with Republicans, it is a small step to suppose that each would like to live next to—or, at any rate, nearby—one another. So, when they move, they sort themselves into politically agreeable communities—or so it is claimed.

Why do people make the choice of where to live that they make? Because they prefer what they prefer—in this case, to live in politically like-minded communities. This is how the narrative—academic as well as popular—of the Big Sort goes. But people searching for a new home, Mummolo and Nall (Reference Mummolo and Nall2017) caution, have many preferences.Footnote 4 Living with politically like-minded neighbors may be one, but many other considerations matter more: affordability, a safe neighborhood, good schools, and living close to work among them. Democrats and Republicans alike prioritize neighborhood quality and affordability.Footnote 5 People do not have endless time to find a new home; they must choose from what is available. As Mummolo and Nall (Reference Mummolo and Nall2017, 57, italics added) rightly noted, “[P]otential movers with a stated propensity to move to more copartisan neighborhoods, regardless of their underlying motivations, are more likely to have few choices [to live in copartisan communities] if they select first on affordability and quality.” The Big Sort narrative fails to reckon with reality-grounded constraints on the alternatives available.

THE ROAD TAKEN

The dominant approach in the study of support for civil liberties is the “least-liked” method of John Sullivan, George Marcus, and their colleagues. Political Tolerance and American Democracy (Sullivan, Piereson, and Marcus Reference Sullivan, Piereson and Marcus1982) and With Malice Toward Some: How People Make Civil Liberties Judgments (Marcus et al. Reference Marcus, Sullivan, Theiss-Morse and Wood1995) are their two landmark works. Because I advocate for an alternative approach, it is even more important to make plain why their work was field defining.

Political tolerance, Sullivan and his colleagues observed, implies a willingness to “put up” with those ideas and people that one intensely dislikes or with whom one intensely disagrees. It is necessary, therefore, to first ensure that people are being asked about groups and ideas that they intensely dislike or with which they intensely disagree. This was simple but brilliant. Like the best ideas, it appears to be just right—after someone has had the creativity to point it out. It revolutionized the study of political tolerance because the least-liked approach is simultaneously a theoretical insight and a measurement procedure. From a list of controversial groups, respondents are asked to choose the group that they dislike most (or like least). Then they are asked whether this group is entitled to a series of rights—for example, whether they should be allowed to teach in public schools, or hold public rallies, or have their phones tapped by the government. The least-liked measurement method has become the preeminent—indeed, in the view of many, the mandatory—method of measuring political tolerance.

Measurement only gets a research project off the ground. Methods must be substantively enlightening. Why has the least-liked method become the dominant way to think about and measure political tolerance? What do we now know that we did not know thanks to the least-liked method? Two standout findings are claimed for it.

The first is the illusion of progress. In his pioneering study of political intolerance at the height of McCarthyism, Samuel Stouffer showed that popular support for civil liberties—although impressively high at the level of abstract principle—melted away in the heat of actual controversies. Even so, reflecting on the changes underway, Stouffer (Reference Stouffer1992) offered a famous prophecy: “Great social, economic, and technological forces are working on the side of exposing ever larger proportions of our population to the idea that ‘people are different from me, with different systems of values, and they can be good people, too.’” Subsequent studies during the 1960s and 1970s showed that levels of political tolerance markedly increased (Davis Reference Davis1975; Nunn, Crockett, and Williams Reference Nunn, Crockett and Williams1978).

Still better times ahead was the forecast, as increasing proportions of Americans became better educated, more geographically mobile, and more exposed to Americans of diverse backgrounds and outlooks. However, Sullivan, Piereson, and Marcus (Reference Sullivan, Piereson and Marcus1982) discovered “a fly in the ointment.” Three decades after Joseph McCarthy’s heyday, communists were no longer the agreed-on threat. Ask Americans about the particular groups that each fears now and they prove to be as politically intolerant as they were in the 1950s. This is a devastating result. The appearance of progress is an illusion. The optimism of the first generation of researchers is a hollow hope. The only thing saving us, Sullivan and his colleagues argued, is the happenstance that we disagree on who we dislike most.

Similarly striking is the second result. It had been supposed that the liberal tradition in American politics provides a measure of support for democratic rights—and, indeed, using traditional measures of support for democratic rights, liberals are more committed than conservatives to an open society. However, if everyone is asked about the group they dislike most, liberals choose groups on the right, conservatives choose groups on the left, and both come up short in supporting the rights of those on the other side of the political fence. Threat perception, it follows, is the key to the politics of tolerance.Footnote 6

THE ROAD NOT TAKEN

In 1960, Herbert McClosky, Paul J. Hoffmann, and Rosemary O’Hara published “Issue Conflict and Consensus Among Party Leaders and Followers.” It was the first large-scale study of the political beliefs and ideological impulses of politically active and influential people. Capitalizing on an innovative survey about the policy beliefs of convention delegates to the presidential nominating conventions in 1956, McClosky and his colleagues brought into the open for the first time the ideological cleavage between the two parties. Democratic delegates were systematically liberal and Republican delegates were systematically conservative over an array of issues, including public ownership of natural resources, government regulation of the economy, equalitarianism and social welfare, tax policy, and foreign policy.Footnote 7 Summarily stated, McClosky et al.’s (Reference McClosky, Hoffmann and O’Hara1960) first landmark discovery was that the politics of the American party system at the elite level is ideological politics.Footnote 8

Reality bites. For voters, the choice is between Democrat/liberal and Republican/conservative. Of course, because the political choices are on offer on these terms, it does not follow that these are the terms on which citizens make their choices. They may mistake or misunderstand what the terms are, supposing that the liberal alternative is the conservative, the conservative is the liberal; or fail to perceive that the liberal–conservative divide runs across issues of civil liberties. Instead, they may respond to them, one by one, as if each is separate and distinct; or take the side that their party advocates simply because their party advocates it; or, even, choose at random a side on an issue because they have not troubled themselves to form a genuine attitude about it.

These possibilities are not merely possible but probable according to the mainstream view that citizens are not capable of engaging politics on ideological terms. They give too little attention to politics, have too little information about it, and are at sea when it comes to knowing what goes with what—let alone why. Their political ideas often are jumbled—if, indeed, they qualify as genuine ideas, given how many citizens appear to choose one side of an issue rather than the other by flipping a coin (Achen and Bartels Reference Achen and Bartels2016; Berelson, Lazarsfeld, and McPhee Reference Berelson, Lazarsfeld and McPhee1954; Campbell et al. Reference Campbell, Converse, Miller and Stokes1960; Converse Reference Converse and Apter1964; Kinder and Kalmoe Reference Kinder and Kalmoe2017; Zaller Reference Zaller1992). Generations of PS101 students have been taught that it is a rookie mistake to suppose that ordinary citizens can engage politics on an ideologically coherent basis—that is, consistently taking liberal or conservative positions on the issues of the day. That, as the saying goes, is the conventional wisdom.

Hence the importance of McClosky and colleagues’ subsequent discoveries (McClosky and Brill Reference McClosky and Brill1982; McClosky and Zaller Reference McClosky and Zaller1982). Purely as a matter of fact, a large portion of the general public has ideological convictions. Those on the left systematically evince an openness to social change, confidence in human nature, and concern for the disadvantaged and distressed. Conversely, those on the right stress the risks of change, the weaknesses and self-indulgence of people in general, and the necessity of individuals to take responsibility for their own lives and overcome their own problems rather than striving for a handout from government.Footnote 9 Moreover, liberal and conservative convictions pervade the political thinking of ordinary citizens, systematically showing up in ideologically coherent stances even on issues of civil liberties and civil rights.

How this is possible I (prudently) leave until the conclusion of this essay. What is vital here are evidentiary credentials for the claim that ordinary citizens take ideologically coherent stances on issues of civil liberties. Figure 1 reproduces a finding from McClosky and Brill’s (Reference McClosky and Brill1982) study of civil liberties—one of a mass of comparable results.Footnote 10 The top panel shows the relationship between ideology (self-designation)Footnote 11 and a multi-indicator measure of support for civil liberties for a large sample of community leaders; the bottom panel shows the same relationship for ordinary citizens.Footnote 12

Figure 1 Ideological Self-Designation and Attitudes Toward Civil Liberties: Community Leaders and Mass Public

Consider first the impact of ideology on support for civil liberties among community leaders. The result is arresting: 87% of liberals score high on the multi-item Index of Civil Liberties, compared to only 35% of conservatives. Conversely, 24% of conservatives score low, compared to only 4% of liberals. It is not a surprise, of course, that the judgments of the politically engaged about civil liberties and civil rights are ideologically grounded. The surprise is shown on the bottom panel: 66% of liberals score high on the Civil Liberties Index, compared to only 23% of conservatives. Conversely, almost half of conservatives (42%) score low, compared to only 11% of liberals. The relationship between identifying as a liberal or as a conservative and consistently taking liberal or conservative positions on issues of civil liberties is not as strong among ordinary citizens as it is among community activists. Nevertheless, it is unmistakable.

This should have been a breakthrough discovery—but no. Like Bishop Berkeley’s tree falling unseen in the forest, in research, esse est percipi—to be is to be perceived. McClosky’s demonstrations of the role of ideology in the political thinking of ordinary citizens have remained unremarked. Even now, in the most ideologically polarized era in American politics in more than a half-century, the mainstream view is that Converse’s (Reference Converse and Apter1964) analysis of the 1950s remains the best mirror of the political thinking of Americans in the 2020s. “Most Americans,” Kinder and Kalmoe (Reference Kinder and Kalmoe2017, 41) concluded in their recent review of research, “are indifferent to or mystified by liberalism and conservatism as political ideas.”

Wrong and a pity. The naked clash of conservative and liberal values is the key to the ferocity of contemporary American politics. Suppose you are a liberal and I am a conservative. If you are truly a liberal, you are not liberal on only one issue but rather on a whole array of issues—and very likely a Democrat to boot. Ditto for me. If I am truly a conservative, I am conservative not on only one issue but on a whole array of issues—and very likely a Republican to boot. We disagree about many things, so we disagree many times—and just so far as our disagreement is grounded in opposing political orientations, our quarrel goes all the way down.

“Most Americans,” Kinder and Kalmoe concluded in their recent review of research, “are indifferent to or mystified by liberalism and conservatism as political ideas.” Wrong and a pity. The naked clash of conservative and liberal values is the key to the ferocity of contemporary American politics.

There is an irony here. According to many political scientists—and still more public pundits—the polarization of American politics is a political fever, the product of raw emotion. This is true for some, but as great a risk for as many or more is the satisfaction of being true to their principles. They know and agree with what their party stands for. Their political faith imprisons them just because it is not blind. So they stand with their side, come what may. Ideological politics is passionate politics because core values are at stake.

INCLUSION OF MUSLIMS AND CONFLICTS BETWEEN LIBERAL VALUES

To understand the choices that citizens make, the starting point should be the choices open to them. In the American party system, the conflict between liberal versus conservative values delimits the choices open for citizens to make on issues of civil liberties. A second illustration of why—to account for the choices that citizens make, the starting point should be the circumstances to which they are responding—is the conflict not between conservative and liberal values but instead between liberal values themselves.

Current research on the inclusion of Muslims documents an array of instances in which majorities of non-Muslims in Western Europe support stripping Muslims of democratic rights (Ivarsflaten and Sniderman Reference Ivarsflaten and Sniderman2022).Footnote 13 The majorities are one sided, often 75% or more refusing to take the Muslims’ side. The countries are all liberal democracies—indeed, among the most supportive of an expansive understanding of the rights of citizens. Moreover, the rights at issue are bedrock democratic rights (i.e., freedom of religion, freedom of speech, and freedom of assembly) confronted not in the abstract but in real life—for example, being allowed to rent a meeting room in a public library.

This may seem an old story. Conflicts between liberal democratic values and some traditional Islamic tenets are well documented (e.g., Norris and Inglehart Reference Norris and Inglehart2002; Sniderman and Hagendoorn Reference Sniderman and Hagendoorn2007). Value conflicts on this order diminish support for the rights of Muslims; however, they do not uproot support for Muslims’ right to hold a public event. Something more is needed to mobilize a one-sided majority against Muslims being allowed to rent a meeting room in a public library.

Conflict with religiously grounded values goes deeper than conflict with cultural values. The gateway question is why. Islamophobia is the “off-the-shelf” answer. Imams are a stereotype magnet—zealots, in the eyes of many non-Muslims, promoters of a crabbed, misogynistic, parochial way of life and religion. Hence, there is an immediate readiness of Islamophobes to oppose Muslims being allowed to rent a meeting room in a public library.

This reasoning is not wrong; it is elliptical. Islamophobes will oppose Muslims being allowed to rent a meeting room in a public library but not because conservative Islamic ideas about the rights and responsibilities of women is the topic. Islamophobes cannot stand Muslims. They oppose their being allowed to use a public library to hold a meeting pretty much whatever the topic. However, Islamophobes are a minority—an angry, agitated minority, but a minority all the same. What needs explanation is why one-sided majorities can be mobilized in opposition to Muslims being allowed to hold a public meeting.

Reality bites is the motif. The fact (and it is a fact) that conservative Muslim ideas about women are religiously grounded values is the “something more.” The insight follows from the theory of speech acts—specifically, the concept of performative utterances. Performative utterances are instances of when “the issue of the utterance is the performing of an action.” Two iconic examples illustrate the idea:

“(E. a) ‘I do (sc. Take this woman to be my lawful wedded wife)’—as uttered in the course of the marriage ceremony.

(E. b) ‘I name this ship the Queen Elizabeth’—as uttered when smashing the bottle against the stern.” (Austin Reference Austin1962, 5)

Speaking the words “I take this woman to be my lawful wedded wife” is not merely to say something; it is to do something. To name a ship is not merely to say something; it is to do something. So, too, is a profession of faith. Both a rabbi declaring “Jews should keep kosher” and an Imam proclaiming “A Muslim should not shake hands with a member of the opposite sex” describe what should be done and call for action to be performed.

Professions of faith are necessarily performative utterances—instances of action as well as expression. Conflicts with religious values thus have two dimensions: substantive and performative. To this point, all eyes have been fixed on the substantive dimension—on the clash between liberal ideals of the larger society and traditional ideals of conservative Muslim communities. What now deserves attention is the performative dimension. Just as affirmations of Islamic ideals that conflict with the liberal ideals of the larger society are calls for compliance, the intensity of the conflict escalates. The combination of what is being urged and the fact that it is being urged generates extreme value conflicts.

Rights are the concern: bedrock claims to freedom of speech and religion. In The Struggle for Inclusion, Ivarsflaten and Sniderman (Reference Ivarsflaten and Sniderman2022) introduce the public rally experiment. The design is 2x2: one factor varies the substantive topic of a rally, uncontroversial or controversial; the other factor is its function, communicative or performative. A nationally representative sample of Norwegians was asked if Muslims should be allowed to hold a public event. The topic of the event was either “Islamic values” or “conservative ideas about women”; its function was either “to explain” or “to preach.”

The reasoning underpinning the design is straightforward: set as a baseline, a low-conflict condition between liberal ideals and traditional Islamic values—a meeting to explain Islamic values. Then, to determine whether the substantive and performative dimensions independently increase the intensity of conflict, there were two more conditions: a public event either to explain “conservative ideas about women” or “to preach” Islamic values. The fourth condition was to determine the combined effect of substantive and performative dimensions: a meeting the purpose of which is to preach rather than to explain, and the topic is “conservative ideas about women” rather than the vaguer “Islamic values.”

Figure 2 shows the results of the experiment. The fourth condition stands apart. In the other three conditions, only a minority opposes allowing Muslims to hold a public rally; in the fourth condition, a majority—indeed, a clear majority: two in every three are opposed. This is an extraordinary turnabout, a volte-face, from decisive support for Muslims being allowed to hold a public rally in the baseline condition to decisive opposition to their doing so in the combined performative/substantive condition.

Figure 2 The Public Rally Experiment

Opposition to the public rally (%).

What accounts for this volte-face, a clear majority in support of Muslims holding a public rally transformed into a clear majority in opposition? The impulse answer is intolerance beneath the surface appearance of tolerance. Figure 3 shows that it is the other way around. The dotted line traces the likelihood of opposing Muslims being allowed to hold a public rally in the baseline condition. The solid line is the likelihood of opposition in the high-conflict condition, conditional on level of tolerance.Footnote 14 The gap between the two lines increases as levels of tolerance increase. Those who are intolerant oppose Muslims being allowed to hold a public rally regardless of the topic or purpose. Those who are tolerant overwhelmingly support their being allowed to do so in the low-conflict condition and overwhelmingly oppose it in the high-conflict condition.

Figure 3 Conflict Between Liberal Values: The Public Rally Experiment

Opposition to the public rally by internal motivation to control the prejudice index.

The dictum of political realism: to explain why people respond as they do, first determine the circumstances to which they are responding. In the low-conflict condition, the tolerant must choose between allowing Muslims to hold a public event to explain Islamic values or opposing it. This is an easy choice for those who are tolerant: say yes, obviously. In contrast, in the high-conflict condition, they must choose between supporting equal rights for Muslims and equal rights for women. Support for equal rights for Muslims and equal rights for women are mutually reinforcing in most circumstances. Moreover, prioritizing equal rights for women is not a manifestation of intolerance. The outcome nevertheless is illiberal, a denial of Muslims’ right to practice their faith. An illiberal outcome, because of support for a liberal value, sounds like a contradiction in terms. In fact, it is testimony to the constraints of political reality.

That is the lesson I tentatively take away from these results. Why tentatively? Because much remains to be done. First, this is the result of one experiment, in one country, at one point in time. Replication is a requirement. Second, there is a self-evident objection. Perhaps those who are tolerant do believe in equal rights for Muslims but this belief is superficial, easily overcome by any rival consideration. Third, and still more concerning, those who are tolerant do not truly believe in equal rights and are only saying what they believe they are supposed to say.

Skepticism is easily aroused. It is not easily quieted. What might provide confidence that those who affirm liberal ideals such as tolerance, yet in particular circumstances oppose equal rights for Muslims, do so on principle? Islam is viewed in Western Europe against a swill of ill will and suspicion of bad faith (Ivarsflaten and Sniderman Reference Ivarsflaten and Sniderman2022, 116–24). It surely is reasonable to ask whether what we have observed are responses to the profession of a religious faith or to the profession of Islam in particular as a religious faith.

Research is underway to answer this question (Bjånesøy et al. Reference Bjånesøy, Esaiasson, Ivarsflaten and Sniderman2023). The logic of a “sincerity” test is worth describing. The overarching claim is that conflicts with religiously grounded values can have two dimensions—performative as well as substantive—and the combination of what is being urged on religious grounds and the fact that it is being urged on religious grounds escalates the conflict. If this is correct, then the same claim on behalf of a religion other than Islam should generate a similar reaction—hence, the design of the public library experiment.

In the public library experiment, a group asks to rent a meeting room in a public library rather than to hold a public event. This provides a pretext. There is a right to hold a public rally; there is no right to rent a meeting room in a public library. The group asking to rent a meeting room is randomly varied. Half of the time, the purpose of the meeting is “to preach conservative Islamic values that homosexuality is a sin.” The other half of the time, the purpose of the meeting is “to preach conservative Christian values that homosexuality is a sin.” Islamic/Christian: that is the only difference.

It was a foregone conclusion that there will be massive opposition to Muslims being allowed to rent the library meeting room to preach that homosexuality is a sin. It is similarly obvious that in a culture as liberal as Norway’s, there will be opposition to Christians preaching that homosexuality is a sin. The question is: “Is the opposition as one-sided and as massive to Christians doing the same thing as Muslims?” Figure 4 shows that the answer is yes. Only a small minority (no more than 20%) of Norwegians believe that Christians should be allowed to rent a meeting room in a public library to preach that homosexuality is a sin. To be sure, on conventional tests of statistical significance, a numerically smaller minority believes that Muslims should be allowed to do the same. This is a poster-prize example of the mistake of relying on conventional tests of statistical significance. Figure 4 shows that 19% (+/-2.0) of Norwegians are willing to rent to Christian fundamentalists, compared to 14% (+/-1.9) who are willing to rent to Muslims—a difference that is not a difference. The sticking point is not the profession of Islam as a faith. It is the profession of faith.

Figure 4 Profession of Islam as a Faith or Profession of Faith?

REALISM: THE MISSING STEP

Mine is a modest proposal: to acknowledge that reality bites. What might it mean to accept it? At the end of a characteristically penetrating and self-assured analysis of the psychology of choice, Simon (Reference Simon1985, 302) upset the apple cart. “We need to understand,” he declared, “not only how people reason about alternatives, but where the alternatives come from in the first place.” The take-away point is that not one but rather two theories are needed—one to account for choice that is conditional on the alternatives available; the other to account for the alternatives available at the moment of choice.

Political realism can take us only so far. One of its virtues, however, is to call out a key mechanism: substantive coordination of alternatives. Consider this old chestnut: the “principle–policy” puzzle. Racial equality at the level of principle is overwhelmingly supported; however, policies to achieve it are sharply contested. This gap between principle and policy, it is asserted, is evidence of the vacuousness of declarations of support for racial equality. White Americans say what they believe they ought to say—but when push comes to shove and an actual effort must be made to accomplish racial equality, they reveal their true colors.

True for some, no doubt.Footnote 15 Still, realism counsels, ask first: What are the alternatives that citizens can choose, when they choose? The policies advertised to achieve racial equality are liberal policies. Why is support for equality at the level of policy rather than at the level of principle? Primarily because conservatives balk at supporting liberal policies (Sniderman, Brody, and Kuklinski Reference Sniderman, Brody, Kuklinski, Sniderman, Brody and Tetlock1992)—which is lamentable supposing that liberals are right. But why should conservatives presume that liberals are right? What is telling is the low probability that political psychologists assign a claim that conservatives reject liberal policies on race because they are conservative.Footnote 16 Politics, for some political psychologists, is substantively content free. Opposition to liberal policies is driven by racism of one variety or another. For a political realist, a relevant point is that the politics of race is a province of the politics of the American party system, and the polarized politics of the American party system is ideological politics. The Democratic party campaigns under the banner of liberalism and the Republican party campaigns under the banner of conservatism, and both are competing for support across the contested issues of the day. Racism is far from extinct—but in an ideological politics, liberals support liberal policies and conservatives support conservative politics on issues of race as well as social welfare. Substantive coordination across as well as within policy domains is the point.

This is how far I have gotten and no farther, without progress in accounting for the dynamics of coordination, still less the generation of alternatives. After a career elaborating a theory accounting for choices conditional on the alternatives on offer, I find it difficult to escape the irony that in an essay arguing for political realism, I have made a case for the need of a theory that can account for what alternatives are on offer.Footnote 17

This is how far I have gotten and no farther, without progress in accounting for the dynamics of coordination, still less the generation of alternatives. After a career elaborating a theory accounting for choices conditional on the alternatives on offer, I find it difficult to escape the irony that in an essay arguing for political realism, I have made a case for the need of a theory that can account for what alternatives are on offer.

CODA

The lecture given in honor of Ithiel de Sola Pool is for a career of work. The lecture itself is a case study of how, as a result of collaboration, one thing has led to another. The focus of my current work is the conflicts between liberal values. But there would be no point in studying how liberals react to conflicts of liberal values if I were not convinced that liberal values have taken hold. I owe this conviction to participating in a study of the Cartoon Crisis of 2005 and 2006 in Denmark. I joined this study only after the creative work—hitting on the very idea of the project, designing the key experiments, superintending the data collection, and discovering the key result—had been done.

The result that my colleagues—Michael Bang Petersen, Rune Slothuus, and Rune Stubager—had discovered was the reason that I joined the project. The Cartoon Crisis had transfixed Danish politics. Even at the most intense moments of the crisis, ordinary Danes, they revealed, were as supportive of the civil liberties of Muslims as of fellow Danes (Sniderman et al. Reference Sniderman, Petersen, Slothuus and Stubager2014). This result astonished me, and I owe my conviction that liberal values are taking hold to it. Standing up for the rights of Muslims, in the heat of the firestorm over the cartoons, is evidence of a “stand-your-ground” commitment to inclusive tolerance.

The democratic experiment remains a bet. For it to continue to pay off sometimes calls for faith that it will continue to pay off. Faith that citizens can keep their moral balance even under stress has underpinned my research since the Cartoon Crisis study—a satisfactorily paradoxical conclusion, I think, for a lecture titled “Political Realism.”

CONFLICTS OF INTEREST

The authors declare no ethical issues or conflicts of interest in this research.

Footnotes

1. The American Association for Public Opinion Research presented Merrill Shanks, Tom Piazza, and Charlie Thomas and their team members with the 2000 Innovators Award for creation of “an on-line system that includes a wealth of data files and documentation [enabling] any user to download the dataset for use with other programs.”

2. For a parallel argument distinguishing ethical realism from ethical moralism, see Hall (Reference Hall2020).

3. For a wide-ranging study of research on affective polarization, see Iyengar et al. (Reference Iyengar, Lelkes, Levundusky, Malhotra and Westwood2019).

4. I owe Mummolo and Nall (Reference Mummolo and Nall2017) for this insight and I follow their argument and analysis.

5. Strictly, Mummolo and Nall (Reference Mummolo and Nall2017) model purchase decisions as elimination by aspect choices.

6. With Malice Toward Some, the second landmark study of the “least-liked method,” probes the neuropsychology of threat perception in the part of the brain implicated in emotional–behavioral responses, especially flight-or-fight reactions. An inability to explain “why some people are more threatened by their foes while others are less threatened” (Gibson Reference Gibson2006, 21) is, to this point, the Achilles’ heel of the least-liked method.

7. Democratic and Republican leaders, to use McClosky’s term, differed significantly on 23 of the 24 national issues. See McClosky, Hoffmann, and O’Hara (Reference McClosky, Hoffmann and O’Hara1960, table III, 422). Administering the same questionnaire to a nationally representative sample of adult Americans, “Issue Conflict” reported only minor differences between Democratic and Republican supporters. Indeed, average Republicans seemed closer in their views to Democratic than Republican delegates.

8. For studies of convention delegates, see, for example, Kirkpatrick (Reference Kirkpatrick1976) and Miller and Jennings (Reference Miller and Jennings1986). For studies of congressional voting, see Poole and Rosenthal (Reference Poole and Rosenthal1997) and McCarty, Poole, and Rosenthal (Reference McCarty, Poole and Rosenthal2016).

9. McClosky and his colleagues had two bedrock advantages: (1) multiple samples of the politically active and the general population responding to identical questionnaires; and (2) multiple multi-indicator measures of liberalism–conservatism that set standards for validity and reliability that have not been matched since. One of the multi-indicator measures of liberalism–conservatism comprises 50 items. For a more recent corroborative study on preference constraint and multi-item measures, see Ansolabehere, Rodden, and Snyder (Reference Ansolabehere, Rodden and Snyder2008).

10. See McClosky and Brill’s (Reference McClosky and Brill1982) figures 7.1–7.4 and tables 7.1–7.9.

11. To maximize the comparability of their results and those of other researchers, I present McClosky and Brill’s (Reference McClosky and Brill1982) results using ideological self-designation as a measure of liberalism–conservatism. It has a double advantage: it is a standard measure of ideology and, as the weakest, it understates the role of ideology in the political thinking of ordinary citizens.

12. The measure of support for civil liberties is excellent. It considers positions on a wide array of issues, among them the rights of “a newspaper to publish its opinions even if they are false or twisted”; “government stepping in to see that minorities receive equal treatment in jobs and housing”; “opposing forcing people to testify against themselves”; and freedom of people “to worship as they please even if their beliefs are extreme” (McClosky and Brill Reference McClosky and Brill1982).

13. For a comprehensive description of methods, see Ivarsflaten and Sniderman (Reference Ivarsflaten and Sniderman2022).

14. Figure 3 reproduces figure 7.2 in Ivarsflaten and Sniderman (Reference Ivarsflaten and Sniderman2022, 115). See The Struggle for Inclusion for a full exposition of measures, samples, and estimation procedures.

15. It is worth noting that the explanatory standard is plausibility, no more. Here, as elsewhere, social desirability bias is evoked without direct evidence of social desirability bias. See Stark, Krosnick, and Scott (Reference Stark, Krosnick, Scott, Krosnick, Stark and Scott2023).

16. For the first and still most deeply thought-through objection that conservatives oppose liberal policies on race for reasons other than conservatism, see Sidanius et al. (Reference Sidanius, Singh, Hetts, Federico, Sears, Sidanius and Bobo2000).

17. A lack of success, but not for lack of effort. Among other attempts, see Sniderman (Reference Sniderman, Lupia, McCubbins and Popkin2000); Sniderman and Bullock (Reference Sniderman, Bullock, Saris and Sniderman2004); Sniderman and Grob (Reference Sniderman and Grob1996); and Sniderman and Levendusky (Reference Sniderman, Levendusky, Dalton and Klingemann2009).

References

REFERENCES

Achen, Christopher H., and Bartels, Larry. 2016. Democracy for Realists. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.10.1515/9781400882731CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ansolabehere, Stephen, Rodden, Jonathan, and Snyder, James M. Jr. 2008. “The Strength of Issues: Using Multiple Measures to Gauge Preference Stability, Ideological Constraint, and Issue Voting.” American Political Science Review 102:215–32.10.1017/S0003055408080210CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Austin, John L. (ed.). 1962. How to Do Things with Words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Berelson, Bernard, Lazarsfeld, Paul F., and McPhee, William N.. 1954. Voting. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Bjånesøy, Lise, Esaiasson, Peter, Ivarsflaten, Elisabeth, and Sniderman, Paul M.. 2023. “Extreme Value Conflicts and Minority Exclusion.” Working paper.Google Scholar
Campbell, Angus, Converse, Philip E., Miller, Warren E., and Stokes, Donald. 1960. The American Voter. New York: John Wiley & Sons, Inc.Google Scholar
Converse, Philip E. 1964. “The Nature of Mass Belief Systems.” In Ideology and Discontent, ed. Apter, David E., 206–61. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Davis, James A. 1975. “Communism, Conformity, Cohorts, and Categories: American Tolerance in 1954 and 1972–73.” American Journal of Sociology 81:491513.10.1086/226105CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibson, James L. 2006. “Enigmas of Intolerance: Fifty Years after Stouffer’s Communism, Conformity, and Civil Liberties.” Perspectives on Politics 4:2134.10.1017/S153759270606004XCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hall, Edward. 2020. Value, Conflict, and Order. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.10.7208/chicago/9780226718453.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardy, Godfrey H. 1940. A Mathematician’s Apology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ivarsflaten, Elisabeth, and Sniderman, Paul M.. 2022. The Struggle for Inclusion. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.10.7208/chicago/9780226807386.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Iyengar, Shanto, Lelkes, Yphtach, Levundusky, Matthew, Malhotra, Neil, and Westwood, Sean. 2019. “Origins and Consequences of Affective Polarization in the United States.” Annual Review of Political Science 22:129–46.10.1146/annurev-polisci-051117-073034CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Iyengar, Shanto, Sood, Gaurav, and Lelkes, Yphtach. 2012. “Affect, Not Ideology.” Public Opinion Quarterly 76:1326–38.10.1093/poq/nfs038CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Iyengar, Shanto, and Westwood, Sean. 2014. “Fear and Loathing across Party Lines: New Evidence on Group Polarization.” American Journal of Political Science 59:690707.10.1111/ajps.12152CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kinder, Donald R., and Kalmoe, Nathan P.. 2017. Neither Liberal nor Conservative. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kirkpatrick, Jeanne. 1976. The New Presidential Elite. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.Google Scholar
Marcus, George E., Sullivan, John L., Theiss-Morse, Elizabeth, and Wood, Sandra L.. 1995. With Malice Toward Some: How People Make Civil Liberties Judgments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9781139174046CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCarty, Nolan, Poole, Keith T., and Rosenthal, Howard. 2016. Polarized America. Boston: MIT Press.Google Scholar
McClosky, Herbert, and Brill, Alida. 1982. Dimensions of Tolerance. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.Google Scholar
McClosky, Herbert, Hoffmann, Paul J., and O’Hara, Rosemary. 1960. “Issue Conflict and Consensus Among Party Leaders and Followers.” American Political Science Review 54:406–27.10.2307/1978302CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McClosky, Herbert, and Zaller, John. 1982. The American Ethos. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, Warren E., and Jennings, M. Kent. 1986. Parties in Transition: A Longitudinal Study of Party Elites and Party Supporters. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.Google Scholar
Mummolo, Jonathan, and Nall, Clayton. 2017. “Why Partisans Do Not Sort: The Constraints on Political Segregation.” Journal of Politics 79:4559.10.1086/687569CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Norris, Pippa, and Inglehart, Ronald F.. 2002. “Islamic Culture and Democracy: Testing the ‘Clash of Civilizations.’Comparative Sociology 1:235–63.Google Scholar
Nunn, Clyde A., Crockett, Harry J., and Williams, J. Allen. 1978. Tolerance for Nonconformity. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.Google Scholar
Poole, Keith T., and Rosenthal, Howard. 1997. Congress. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sidanius, Jim, Singh, Pam, Hetts, John J., and Federico, Chris. 2000. “It’s Not Affirmative Action, It’s the Blacks.” In Racialized Politics, ed. Sears, David O., Sidanius, Jim, and Bobo, Lawrence, chap. 7. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Simon, Herbert A. 1985. “Human Nature in Politics: The Dialogue of Psychology with Political Science.” American Political Science Review 79:293304.10.2307/1956650CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sniderman, Paul M. 2000. “Taking Sides: A Fixed Choice Theory of Political Reasoning.” In Elements of Reason: Cognition, Choice, and the Bounds of Rationality, ed. Lupia, Arthur, McCubbins, Mathew D., and Popkin, Samuel L., 6784. New York: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511805813.004CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sniderman, Paul M., Brody, Richard A., and Kuklinski, James H.. 1992. “The Principle–Policy Puzzle: The Paradox of American Racial Attitudes.” In Reasoning and Choice, ed. Sniderman, Paul M., Brody, Richard A., and Tetlock, Philip E., 5869. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sniderman, Paul M., and Bullock, John G.. 2004. “A Consistency Theory of Public Opinion and Political Choice: The Hypothesis of Menu Dependence.” In Studies in Public Opinion, ed. Saris, Willem and Sniderman, Paul M., 337–57. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.10.1515/9780691188386-014CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sniderman, Paul M., and Grob, Douglas. 1996. “Innovations in Experimental Design in General Population Attitude Surveys.” Annual Review of Sociology 22:377–99.10.1146/annurev.soc.22.1.377CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sniderman, Paul M., and Hagendoorn, Louk. 2007. When Ways of Life Collide. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Sniderman, Paul M., and Levendusky, Matthew S.. 2009. “An Institutional Theory of Political Choice.” In The Oxford Handbook of Political Behavior, ed. Dalton, Russell J. and Klingemann, Hans-Dieter, 437–56. New York: Oxford University Press.10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199270125.003.0023CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sniderman, Paul M., Petersen, Michael Bang, Slothuus, Rune, and Stubager, Rune. 2014. Paradoxes of Liberal Democracy: Islam, Western Europe, and the Danish Cartoon Crisis. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.10.23943/princeton/9780691161105.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stark, Tobias H., Krosnick, Jon A., and Scott, Amanda L.. 2023. “Taking Stock: Explicit and Implicit Prejudice.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Implicit Bias and Racism, ed. Krosnick, Jon A., Stark, Tobias, and Scott, Amanda L.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Stouffer, Samuel A. 1992. Communism, Conformity and Civil Liberties. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Press.Google Scholar
Sullivan, John L., Piereson, James E., and Marcus, George E.. 1982. Political Tolerance and American Democracy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Zaller, John. 1992. The Nature and Origins of Mass Opinion. New York: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511818691CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1 Ideological Self-Designation and Attitudes Toward Civil Liberties: Community Leaders and Mass Public

Figure 1

Figure 2 The Public Rally ExperimentOpposition to the public rally (%).

Figure 2

Figure 3 Conflict Between Liberal Values: The Public Rally ExperimentOpposition to the public rally by internal motivation to control the prejudice index.

Figure 3

Figure 4 Profession of Islam as a Faith or Profession of Faith?