Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T09:08:20.469Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Revisiting closed asymptotic couples

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 June 2022

Matthias Aschenbrenner
Affiliation:
Kurt Gödel Research Center for Mathematical Logic, Universität Wien, 1090 Wien, Austria ([email protected])
Lou van den Dries
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematics, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, Urbana, IL 61801, USA ([email protected])
Joris van der Hoeven
Affiliation:
CNRS, LIX, École Polytechnique, 91128 Palaiseau Cedex, France ([email protected])
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Every discrete definable subset of a closed asymptotic couple with ordered scalar field ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ is shown to be contained in a finite-dimensional ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-linear subspace of that couple. It follows that the differential-valued field $\mathbb {T}$ of transseries induces more structure on its value group than what is definable in its asymptotic couple equipped with its scalar multiplication by real numbers, where this asymptotic couple is construed as a two-sorted structure with $\mathbb {R}$ as the underlying set for the second sort.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on Behalf of The Edinburgh Mathematical Society

Introduction

The field of Laurent series with real coefficients comes with a natural derivation but is too small to be closed under integration and exponentiation. These defects are cured by passing to a certain canonical extension, the ordered differential field $\mathbb {T}$ of transseries. Transseries are formal series in an indeterminate $x>\mathbb {R}$, such as

\begin{align*} & - 3 \operatorname{e}^{\operatorname{e}^x} + \operatorname{e}^{\textstyle\frac{\operatorname{e}^x}{\log x} +\frac{\operatorname{e}^x}{\log^2 x} + \frac{\operatorname{e}^x}{\log^3 x} + \cdots} - x^{11} + 7\\ & \quad+ \frac{\pi}{x} + \frac{1}{x \log x} + \frac{1}{x \log^2 x} + \frac{1}{x \log^3 x} + \cdots \\ & \quad+ \frac{2}{x^2} + \frac{6}{x^3} + \frac{24}{x^4} +\frac{120}{x^5} + \frac{720}{x^6} + \cdots\\ & \quad + \operatorname{e}^{- x} + 2 \operatorname{e}^{- x^2} + 3 \operatorname{e}^{- x^3} + 4 \operatorname{e}^{- x^4} + \cdots, \end{align*}

where $\log ^2 x := (\log x)^2$, etc. Transseries, that is, elements of $\mathbb {T}$, are also the logarithmic-exponential series ($\operatorname {LE}$-series, for short) from [Reference van den Dries, Macintyre and Marker4]; we refer to that paper, or to Appendix A of our book [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2], for a detailed construction of $\mathbb {T}$.

What we need for now is that $\mathbb {T}$ is a real closed field extension of the field $\mathbb {R}$ of real numbers and that $\mathbb {T}$ comes equipped with a distinguished element $x>\mathbb {R}$, an exponential operation $\exp \colon \mathbb {T} \to \mathbb {T}$ and a distinguished derivation $\partial \colon \mathbb {T}\to \mathbb {T}$. The exponentiation here is an isomorphism of the ordered additive group of $\mathbb {T}$ onto the ordered multiplicative group $\mathbb {T}^{>}$ of positive elements of $\mathbb {T}$; we set $\operatorname {e}^f:=\exp (f)$ for $f\in \mathbb {T}$. The derivation $\partial$ comes from differentiating a transseries termwise with respect to $x$, and we set $f':= \partial (f)$, $f'':= \partial ^2(f)$, and so on, for $f\in \mathbb {T}$; thus, $x'=1$, and $\partial$ is compatible with exponentiation: $(\operatorname {e}^f)'=f'\operatorname {e}^f$ for $f\in \mathbb {T}$. Moreover, the constant field of $\mathbb {T}$ is $\mathbb {R}$, that is, $\{f\in \mathbb {T}:\,f'=0\}=\mathbb {R}$; see again [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2] for details. Before stating our new results, we introduce some conventions:

Notations and conventions. Throughout, $m$, $n$ range over $\mathbb {N}=\{0,\,1,\,2,\,\ldots \}$. Ordered sets, ordered abelian groups, and ordered fields are totally ordered, by convention. Given an ambient ordered set $S$, a downward closed subset of $S$, also called a cut in $S$, is a set $D\subseteq S$ such that for all $a,\,b\in S$ with $a < b\in D$ we have $a\in D$. For an (additively written) ordered abelian group $\varGamma$ we set

\[ \varGamma^{\ne}\ :=\ \varGamma\setminus \{0\}, \quad \varGamma^{<}\ :=\ \{\gamma\in \varGamma:\,\gamma<0\}, \qquad \varGamma^{>}\ :=\ \{\gamma\in \varGamma:\,\gamma>0\}. \]

For any field $K$ we let $K^\times =K\setminus \{0\}$ be its multiplicative group. A differential field is a field $K$ of characteristic $0$ with a derivation $\partial \colon K \to K$, and we set $a':= \partial (a)$ for $a\in K$, and let $b^{\dagger} :=b'/b$ be the logarithmic derivative of $b\in K^\times$ when the ambient differential field $K$ with its derivation $\partial$ is clear from the context; note that then $(ab)^{\dagger} =a^{\dagger} + b^{\dagger}$ for $a,\,b\in K^\times$.

Our book [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2] culminated in an elimination theory for the differential field $\mathbb {T}$ of transseries. As a consequence, we found that the induced structure on its constant field $\mathbb {R}$ is just its semialgebraic structure: if $X\subseteq \mathbb {R}^n$ is definable in $\mathbb {T}$, then $X$ is semialgebraic (in the sense of $\mathbb {R}$). (Here and throughout “definable in $\mathbf {M}$” means “definable in $\mathbf {M}$ with parameters from $\mathbf {M}$”.)

The story is more complicated for the structure induced by $\mathbb {T}$ on its value group. To explain this, we recall that the natural valuation ring

\[ \mathcal{O}_{\mathbb{T}} = \ \big\{f\in \mathbb{T}:\, |f|\leqslant r \text{ for some real }r>0\big\} \]

of the real closed field $\mathbb {T}$ is clearly $0$-definable in $\mathbb {T}$ as a differential field, which is how we construe $\mathbb {T}$ in the rest of this paper. Let $v\colon \mathbb {T}^\times \to \Gamma _{\mathbb {T}}$ be the corresponding valuation on the field $\mathbb {T}$. We may consider $\Gamma _{\mathbb {T}}$ as the quotient ${\mathbb {T}^\times }\!/\negmedspace \asymp$ and $v$ as the natural map to this quotient where $\asymp$ is a $0$-definable equivalence relation on $\mathbb {T}^\times$.

Thus, $\Gamma _{\mathbb {T}}$ is part of $\mathbb {T}^{\operatorname {eq}}$. What is the structure induced by $\mathbb {T}$ on $\Gamma _{\mathbb {T}}$? It includes the structure of $\Gamma _{\mathbb {T}}$ as an ordered (by convention, additively written) abelian group. Moreover, the derivation of $\mathbb {T}$ induces a function $\psi \colon \Gamma _{\mathbb {T}}^{\ne } \to \Gamma _{\mathbb {T}}$ by $\psi (vf)=v(f^{\dagger} )$ for $f\in \mathbb {T}^\times$ with $vf\ne 0$. The structure $(\Gamma _{\mathbb {T}},\, \psi )$ consisting of the ordered abelian group $\Gamma _{\mathbb {T}}$ with the function $\psi$ is the asymptotic couple of $\mathbb {T}$, a notion introduced for differential-valued fields – among which is $\mathbb {T}$—by Rosenlicht [Reference Rosenlicht7]. There is also a natural $0$-definable scalar multiplication

\[ (r,\gamma)\mapsto r\gamma:\,\mathbb{R}\times \Gamma_{\mathbb{T}}\to \Gamma_{\mathbb{T}} \]

that makes $\Gamma _{\mathbb {T}}$ into a vector space over $\mathbb {R}$; it is given by $rv(f)=v(f^r)$ for $f\in \mathbb {T}^{>}$, and the reason it is $0$-definable (in $\mathbb {T}^{\operatorname {eq}}$) is that $r\alpha =\beta$ (for $r\in \mathbb {R}$ and $\alpha,\, \beta \in \Gamma _{\mathbb {T}}$) iff there are $f,\,g\in \mathbb {T}^{\times }$ such that $\alpha =vf$, $\beta =vg$ and $rf^{\dagger} =g^{\dagger}$. For this reason, we consider the $2$-sorted structure $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }_{\mathbb {T}}=((\Gamma _{\mathbb {T}},\,\psi ),\, \mathbb {R}; \operatorname {sc}\!)$ consisting of the asymptotic couple $(\Gamma _{\mathbb {T}},\,\psi )$, the field $\mathbb {R}$, and the above scalar multiplication

\[ \operatorname{sc}\colon \mathbb{R}\times \Gamma_{\mathbb{T}}\to \Gamma_{\mathbb{T}}, \quad\operatorname{sc}(r,\gamma)=r\gamma. \]

The basic elementary properties of this $2$-sorted structure were determined in [Reference Aschenbrenner and van den Dries1]. This structure encodes important features of $\mathbb {T}$, and in this paper, we prove a new result about it in § 5:

Theorem 0.1 Let $\Gamma _{\mathbb {T}}$ be equipped with its order topology, and let $X\subseteq \Gamma _{\mathbb {T}}$ be definable in $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }_{\mathbb {T}}$. Then the following are equivalent:

  1. (i) $X$ is contained in a finite-dimensional $\mathbb {R}$-linear subspace of $\Gamma _{\mathbb {T}};$

  2. (ii) $X$ is discrete;

  3. (iii) $X$ has an empty interior in $\Gamma _{\mathbb {T}}$.

We also know from [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2, Corollaries 14.3.10, 14.3.11] that for any non-zero differential polynomial $G(Y)\in \mathbb {T}\{Y\}$ the subset $\big \{vy:\,y\in \mathbb {T}^\times,\,\ G(y)=0\big \}$ of $\Gamma _{\mathbb {T}}$ is discrete. The set of zeros of

\[ G(Y):= Y^2Y'Y^{(3)}-Y^2(Y^{(2)})^2-Y(Y')^2Y^{(2)}+(Y')^4 \]

in $\mathbb {T}$ is

\[ \big\{a\operatorname{e}^{b\operatorname{e}^{cx}}:\,a,b,c\in \mathbb{R}\big\}\cup \big\{a\operatorname{e}^{bx}:\,a,b\in \mathbb{R}\big\}. \]

For this $G$ the set $\big \{vy:\,y\in \mathbb {T}^\times,\,\ G(y)=0\big \}$ is not contained in a finite-dimensional $\mathbb {R}$-linear subspace of $\Gamma _{\mathbb {T}}$ and thus not definable in the $2$-sorted structure $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }_{\mathbb {T}}$ by the theorem above. We treat this example in more detail at the end of § 1.

The authors of [Reference Aschenbrenner and van den Dries1] had speculated that the subsets of $\Gamma _{\mathbb {T}}$ definable in $\mathbb {T}^{\operatorname {eq}}$ might be just those that are definable in the $2$-sorted structure $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }_{\mathbb {T}}$. The above is a counter example but leaves open the possibility that $\Gamma _{\mathbb {T}}$ is stably embedded in $\mathbb {T}^{\operatorname {eq}}$. In this connection, we note that for all intents and purposes, we can replace the $2$-sorted structure $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }_{\mathbb {T}}$ by the $1$-sorted structure $(\Gamma _{\mathbb {T}};\psi,\,\mathbb {R} 1,\,\operatorname {sc})$ consisting of the asymptotic couple $(\Gamma _{\mathbb {T}}; \psi )$ expanded by the set $\mathbb {R} 1\subseteq \Gamma _{\mathbb {T}}$, where $1=v(x^{-1})\in \Gamma _{\mathbb {T}}^{>}$ is the unique fixed point of $\psi$, and by the function

\[ \operatorname{sc}\ :\,(\mathbb{R} 1)\times \Gamma_{\mathbb{T}}\to \Gamma_{\mathbb{T}}, \quad \operatorname{sc}(r1,\gamma) := r\gamma. \]

Why revisit closed asymptotic couples?

The proof of Theorem 0.1 requires the results of [Reference Aschenbrenner and van den Dries1], suitably extended. This was our original motive for revisiting the subject of closed asymptotic couples. The theorem itself is of interest but is also needed for its application to the induced structure on the value group of $\mathbb {T}$.

The quantifier elimination (QE) for closed asymptotic couples in [Reference Aschenbrenner and van den Dries1] was expected to help in obtaining a QE for $\mathbb {T}$. The latter is achieved in [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2, Chapter 16], but there we needed only a key lemma from [Reference Aschenbrenner and van den Dries1], not its QE for closed asymptotic couples. That key lemma is [Reference Aschenbrenner and van den Dries1, Property B], and is given a self-contained proof of five dense pages in [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2, § 9.9]. Since then, we found a simpler way to obtain the QE in [Reference Aschenbrenner and van den Dries1] that does not use the key lemma alluded to but depends on some easier-to-prove new lemmas that have also other applications; see § 2. This new proof of QE, given in § 3, is another reason for revisiting the subject of closed asymptotic couples. (We derive the “key lemma” itself as a routine consequence of the QE for closed asymptotic couples: Proposition 6.3.)

For his study of transexponential pre-$H$-fields in [Reference Pynn-Coates6, Chapter 6] and [Reference Pynn-Coates5], Nigel Pynn-Coates introduced a modified version of “closed asymptotic couple” and adapted accordingly some material from our (unpublished) 2017 version of this paper. Getting the paper published is also more urgent now because in our recent proof that maximal Hardy fields are $\eta _1$ we use results from § 4 below.

Finally, this paper gives us an opportunity to enhance and better organize parts of [Reference Aschenbrenner and van den Dries1], and acknowledge gaps in some proofs there; we intend to close these gaps in a follow-up to the present paper. No familiarity with [Reference Aschenbrenner and van den Dries1] is needed, but we do assume as background some 20 pages (mainly on asymptotic couples) from [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2], namely parts of § 2.4 on ordered abelian groups, Sections 6.5, 9.1 (subsection on asymptotic couples), 9.2 (first four pages), and 9.8. For the reader's convenience, we also repeat definitions of key notions concerning asymptotic couples and $H$-fields.

We thank Nigel Pynn-Coates for his careful reading of this paper, and corrections, and the referee for helpful comments.

1. Preliminaries

We only consider asymptotic couples of $H$-type, calling them $H$-couples for brevity. Thus, an $H$-couple is a pair $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ consisting of an ordered abelian group $\Gamma$ with a map $\psi \colon \Gamma ^{\ne }\to \Gamma$, such that for all $\alpha,\,\beta \in \Gamma ^{\ne }$,

  1. (AC1) $\alpha +\beta \ne 0\ \Longrightarrow \ \psi (\alpha +\beta )\geqslant \min \!(\psi (\alpha ),\,\psi (\beta ))$;

  2. (AC2) $\psi (k\alpha )=\psi (\alpha )$ for all $k\in \mathbb {Z}^{\ne }$;

  3. (AC3) $\alpha >0\ \Longrightarrow \alpha +\psi (\alpha )> \psi (\beta )$;

  4. (HC) $0<\alpha \leqslant \beta \ \Longrightarrow \ \psi (\alpha )\geqslant \psi (\beta )$.

(As an aside, note that (AC2) and (HC) together imply (AC1); had we observed this earlier, it would have shortened some arguments in [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2, § 9.8]; the reader can use it to the same effect in § 2 of the present paper.) Let $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ be an $H$-couple. By (AC1) and (AC2) the function $\psi$ is a valuation on the abelian group $\Gamma$; as usual, we extend $\psi$ to $\psi \colon \Gamma \to \Gamma _{\infty }:=\Gamma \cup \{\infty \}$ by $\psi (0):= \infty$; we use $\alpha ^{\dagger}$ as an alternative notation for $\psi (\alpha )$ and set $\alpha ':=\alpha +\alpha ^{\dagger}$ for $\alpha \in \Gamma$. Also $\Psi := \psi (\Gamma ^{\ne })$. We recall from [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2, Corollary 9.2.16] a basic trichotomy for $H$-couples which says that we are in exactly one of the following three cases:

  • $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ has a (necessarily unique) gap, that is, an element $\gamma \in \Gamma$ such that $\Psi < \gamma < (\Gamma ^{>})'$;

  • $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ is grounded, that is, $\Psi$ has a largest element;

  • $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ has asymptotic integration, that is, $\Gamma =(\Gamma ^{\ne })'$.

We say that $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ is closed if $\Gamma$ is divisible, $\Psi \subseteq \Gamma$ is downward closed, and $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ has asymptotic integration. We also use the qualifiers having a gap, grounded, having asymptotic integration, and closed for $H$-couples with extra structure.

An $H$-cut in $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ is a downward closed set $P\subseteq \Gamma$ such that $\Psi \subseteq P<(\Gamma ^{>})'$. The set $\Psi ^{\downarrow }:=\{\alpha \in \Gamma :\, \alpha \leqslant \beta for some \beta \in \Psi \}$ is an $H$-cut in $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$, and if $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ is grounded or has asymptotic integration, this is the only $H$-cut in $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$. If $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ has a gap $\beta$, then $\Psi ^{\downarrow }\cup \{\beta \}$ is the only other $H$-cut in $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$.

In particular, if $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ is closed, then $\Psi$ is the only $H$-cut in $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$, but in eliminating quantifiers for closed $H$-couples in § 3, it is essential to have a predicate for this $H$-cut in our language.

Where do closed $H$-couples come from?

We recall from [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2, Chapter 10] that an $H$-field is an ordered differential field $K$ with constant field $C$ such that:

  1. (H1) $a'>0$ for all $a\in K$ with $a>C$;

  2. (H2) $\mathcal {O}=C+ o$, where $\mathcal {O}$ is the convex hull of $C$ in the ordered field $K$, and $ o$ is the maximal ideal of the valuation ring $\mathcal {O}$.

Let $K$ be an $H$-field, and let $\mathcal {O}$ and $o$ be as in (H2). Thus, $K$ is a valued field with valuation ring $\mathcal {O}$. Let $v\colon K^\times \to \Gamma$ be the associated valuation. The value group $\Gamma =v(K^\times )$ is made into an $H$-couple $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$—the $H$-couple of $K$—by $\psi (vf):=v(f^{\dagger} )$ for $f\in K^\times$ with $vf\ne 0$. We call $K$ Liouville closed if it is real closed and for all $a\in K$ there exists $b\in K$ with $a=b'$ and also a $b\in K^\times$ such that $a=b^{\dagger}$.

If $K$ is Liouville closed, its $H$-couple is closed as is easily verified. We recall from [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2] that $\mathbb {T}$ is a Liouville closed $H$-field.

Ordered vector spaces

Throughout we let ${\boldsymbol {k}}$, ${\boldsymbol {k}}_0$, and ${\boldsymbol {k}}^*$ be ordered fields. Recall that an ordered vector space over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ is an ordered abelian group $\Gamma$ with a scalar multiplication ${\boldsymbol {k}}\times \Gamma \to \Gamma$ that makes $\Gamma$ into a vector space over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ such that $c\gamma >0$ for all $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}^{>}$ and $\gamma \in \Gamma ^{>}$. Let $\Gamma$ be an ordered vector space over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$. Then any ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-linear subspace of $\Gamma$ is considered as an ordered vector space over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ in the obvious way. We shall need the following easy result about $\Gamma$:

Lemma 1.1 Let $\Gamma _0$ be a ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-linear subspace of $\Gamma$. Suppose $\Gamma$ contains an element $\varepsilon$ with $0 < \varepsilon < \Gamma _0^{>}$. Then $\Gamma _0$ is closed in $\Gamma$ with respect to the order topology on $\Gamma$.

Proof. Let $\gamma \in \Gamma \setminus \Gamma _0$. With $\varepsilon$ as in the hypothesis, we observe that the interval ${(\gamma -\varepsilon,\, \gamma +\varepsilon )}$ can have at most one point in it from $\Gamma _0$, and so by decreasing $\varepsilon$ we can arrange that $(\gamma -\varepsilon,\, \gamma +\varepsilon )\cap \Gamma _0=\emptyset$.

The ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-archimedean class of $\alpha \in \Gamma$ is

\[ [\alpha]_{{\boldsymbol{k}}}\ :=\ \big\{\gamma\in \Gamma:\, \lvert\gamma\rvert \leqslant c\lvert\alpha\rvert\text{ and }\lvert\alpha\rvert \leqslant c\lvert\gamma\rvert\text{ for some }c\in {\boldsymbol{k}}^{>}\big\}. \]

Let $[\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ be the set of ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-archimedean classes. Then $[\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ is a partition of $\Gamma$, and we linearly order $[\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ by

\begin{align*} [\alpha]_{{\boldsymbol{k}}}<[\beta]_{{\boldsymbol{k}}} & \quad:\Longleftrightarrow\quad c\lvert\alpha\rvert<\lvert\beta\rvert\text{ for all }c\in {\boldsymbol{k}}^{>} \\ & \quad \Longleftrightarrow\quad [\alpha]_{{\boldsymbol{k}}}\neq [\beta]_{{\boldsymbol{k}}}\text{ and }\lvert\alpha\rvert<\lvert\beta\rvert. \end{align*}

Thus, $[0]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=\{0\}$ is the smallest ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-archimedean class. For $\alpha,\,\beta \in \Gamma$, $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}^\times$ we have $[c\alpha ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\alpha ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ and $[\alpha +\beta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}} \leqslant \max ([\alpha ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}},\,[\beta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}})$, with equality if $[\alpha ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\neq [\beta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$.

Lemma 1.2 Let $\Gamma \ne \{0\}$ be an ordered vector space over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ such that $[\Gamma ^{\ne }]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ has no least element. Then every finite-dimensional ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-linear subspace of $\Gamma$ is discrete with respect to the order topology on $\Gamma$.

Proof. First note that if $\gamma _1,\,\ldots,\,\gamma _n\in \Gamma ^{\ne }$ and $[\gamma _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}},\,\ldots,\,[\gamma _n]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ are distinct, then $\gamma _1,\,\ldots,\,\gamma _n$ are ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-linearly independent. Thus, for a finite-dimensional ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-linear subspace $\Delta \ne \{0\}$ of $\Gamma$ we can take $\delta \in \Delta ^{\ne }$ such that $[\delta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ is minimal in $[\Delta ^{\ne }]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. Then for any $\alpha \in \Delta$ and $\beta \in \Gamma ^{\ne }$ with $[\beta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}<[\delta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ we have $\alpha +\beta \notin \Delta$.

Lemma 1.2 takes care of the easy direction (i) $\Rightarrow$ (ii) in Theorem 0.1. The direction (ii) $\Rightarrow$ (iii) is trivial. The harder direction (iii) $\Rightarrow$ (i) uses a generality on expanded vector spaces, to which we now turn.

Let $V$ be a vector space over a field $C$. We consider the two-sorted structure $(V,\,C;\operatorname {sc})$ consisting of the abelian group $V$, the field $C$, and the scalar multiplication $\operatorname {sc}\colon C\times V \to V$ of the vector space $V$. Let $X\subseteq V$. Then we have the expansion $\mathbf {V}=((V,\,X),\,C;\operatorname {sc}\!)$ of $(V,\,C;\operatorname {sc})$. Let $\mathbf {V}^*=((V^*,\, X^*),\, C^*;\operatorname {sc}\!)$ be an elementary extension of $\mathbf {V}$. Let $C^* V$ be the $C^*$-linear subspace of $V^*$ spanned by $V$.

Lemma 1.3 Assume $\mathbf {V}^*$ is $|V|^+$-saturated. Then $X$ is contained in a finite-dimensional $C$-linear subspace of $V$ if and only if $X^*\subseteq C^*V$.

Proof. If $X\subseteq Cv_1+\cdots + Cv_n$, $v_1,\,\ldots,\, v_n\in V$, then $X^*\subseteq C^*v_1+\cdots + C^*v_n\subseteq C^*V$. We prove the contrapositive of the other direction, so assume $X\not \subseteq Cv_1+\cdots +Cv_n$ for all $v_1,\,\ldots,\, v_n\in V$. Then $X^*\not \subseteq C^*v_1+\cdots +C^*v_n$ for all $v_1,\,\ldots,\, v_n\in V$, and so by saturation we get an element of $X^*$ that does not lie in $C^*V$.

For certain $(V,\,C;\operatorname {sc})$ this will be applied to sets $X\subseteq V$ that are definable in a suitable expansion of $(V,\,C;\operatorname {sc})$, with $X^*$ the corresponding set in an elementary extension of that expansion.

$H$-couples over ordered fields

Ordered vector spaces come into play as follows. Let $K$ be a Liouville closed $H$-field. It has the (ordered) constant field $C$, and the $H$-couple $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$. We have a map $(c,\,\gamma )\mapsto c\gamma \colon C\times \Gamma \to \Gamma$ such that $cvf=vg$ whenever $f,\,g\in K^\times$ and $cf^{\dagger} =g^{\dagger}$. This map makes $\Gamma$ into an ordered vector space over $C$, and $\psi (c\gamma )=\psi (\gamma )$ for all $c\in C^\times$ and $\gamma \in \Gamma ^{\ne }$.

Accordingly, we define an $H$-couple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ to be an $H$-couple $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ where the ordered abelian group $\Gamma$ is also equipped with a map ${\boldsymbol {k}}\times \Gamma \to \Gamma$ making $\Gamma$ into an ordered vector space over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ such that $\psi (c\gamma )=\psi (\gamma )$ for all $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}^\times$ and $\gamma \in \Gamma ^{\ne }$. Thus, the $H$-couple of a Liouville closed $H$-field is naturally an $H$-couple over its constant field.

Let $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ be an $H$-couple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$. A basic fact is that for distinct $\alpha,\,\beta \in \Gamma ^{\ne }$ we have $[\psi (\alpha )-\psi (\beta )]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}} < [\alpha -\beta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$, since for all $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}^{>}$, we have $\psi (\alpha )-\psi (\beta )=\psi (c\alpha )-\psi (c\beta )=o(c(\alpha -\beta ))$, by [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2, 6.5.4(ii)]. Note also that for all $\alpha,\,\beta \in \Gamma ^{\ne }$,

\[ [\alpha]_{{\boldsymbol{k}}}=[\beta]_{{\boldsymbol{k}}}\ \Longrightarrow\ \psi(\alpha)=\psi(\beta). \]

Hahn spaces

These are the ordered Hahn spaces from [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2, § 2.4]: a Hahn space $\Gamma$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ is an ordered vector space over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ such that for all $\alpha,\,\beta \in \Gamma ^{\neq }$ with $[\alpha ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\beta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ there exists $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}^\times$ such that $[\alpha -c\beta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}<[\alpha ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$.

Examples

  1. (1) Any one-dimensional ordered vector space over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ is a Hahn space over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$.

  2. (2) Any ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-linear subspace of a Hahn space over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ is a Hahn space over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$.

  3. (3) Any ordered vector space over the ordered field $\mathbb {R}$ is a Hahn space over $\mathbb {R}$.

  4. (4) The ordered $\mathbb {Q}$-vector space $\mathbb {Q}+\mathbb {Q}\sqrt 2 \subseteq \mathbb {R}$ is not a Hahn space over $\mathbb {Q}$.

We say that an $H$-couple $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ is of Hahn type if for all $\alpha,\,\beta \in \Gamma ^{\ne }$ with $\psi (\alpha )=\psi (\beta )$ there exists a scalar $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}$ such that $\psi (\alpha -c\beta )> \psi (\alpha )$; equivalently, $\Gamma$ is a Hahn space over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ and for all $\alpha,\,\beta \in \Gamma ^{\ne }$,

\[ \psi(\alpha)=\psi(\beta)\ \Longrightarrow\ [\alpha]_{\boldsymbol{k}}=[\beta]_{\boldsymbol{k}}. \]

Let $K$ be a Liouville closed $H$-field. We made its $H$-couple $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$ into an $H$-couple over its constant field $C$, and as such $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ is of Hahn type.

Details on the example in the introduction

We consider the Liouville closed $H$-field $\mathbb {T}$ and its element $x$ with $x'=1$. For $z\in \mathbb {T}$ with $z'\notin \mathbb {R}$ we have

\begin{align*} zz'' = (z')^2 & \Longleftrightarrow\ z^{\dagger}{=} (z')^{\dagger}\ \Longleftrightarrow\ (z'/z)^{\dagger}{=} 0\ \Longleftrightarrow\ z'=tz \text{ for some }t\in \mathbb{R}^{{\times}}\\ & \Longleftrightarrow\ z=s\operatorname{e}^{tx} \text{ for some }s,t\in \mathbb{R}^\times. \end{align*}

Considering also the case where $z'\in \mathbb {R}$ we conclude that

\[ \big\{z\in \mathbb{T}:\, zz''=(z')^2\big\} = \big\{s\operatorname{e}^{tx}:\, s,t\in \mathbb{R}\big\}. \]

Next, let $y\in \mathbb {T}^\times$ and suppose $z:=y^{\dagger}$ satisfies $zz''=(z')^2$. Then $y=r\operatorname {e}^{u}$ for some $r\in \mathbb {R}$ and $u\in \mathbb {T}$ with $u'=z$. For $z=s\operatorname {e}^{tx}$ with $s,\,t\in \mathbb {R}$ and $u\in \mathbb {T}$, $u'=z$ we get $u\in \mathbb {R}\operatorname {e}^{tx}+\mathbb {R}$ if $t\ne 0$, and $u\in \mathbb {R} x+\mathbb {R}$ if $t=0$. Hence $y=a\operatorname {e}^{b\operatorname {e}^{cx}}$ or $y=a\operatorname {e}^{bx}$ for some $a,\,b,\,c\in \mathbb {R}$. From $zz''=(z')^2$ we get

\[ y^2y'y^{(3)}-y^2(y^{(2)})^2-y(y')^2y^{(2)}+(y')^4=0. \]

In this way, we get for

\[ G(Y):=Y^2Y'Y^{(3)}-Y^2(Y^{(2)})^2-Y(Y')^2Y^{(2)}+(Y')^4 \]

that its set of zeros in $\mathbb {T}$ is

\[ \big\{a\operatorname{e}^{b\operatorname{e}^{cx}}:\, a,b,c\in \mathbb{R}\big\}\cup \big\{a\operatorname{e}^{bx}:\, a,b\in \mathbb{R}\big\}. \]

It is easy to see that for $0< c < d$ in $\mathbb {R}$ we have $[v(\operatorname {e}^{\operatorname {e}^{cx}})]_{\mathbb {R}} < [v(\operatorname {e}^{\operatorname {e}^{dx}})]_{\mathbb {R}}$, so the set $\big \{vy:\, y\in \mathbb {T}^\times,\,\ G(y)=0\big \}$ is not contained in a finite-dimensional $\mathbb {R}$-linear subspace of $\Gamma _{\mathbb {T}}$.

2. Extensions of $H$-couples

In this section, $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ and $(\Gamma _1,\, \psi _1)$ are $H$-couples over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$. An embedding

\[ h \colon\ (\Gamma,\psi) \to (\Gamma_1,\psi_1) \]

is an embedding $h \colon \Gamma \to \Gamma _1$ of ordered vector spaces over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ such that

\[ h\bigl(\psi(\gamma)\bigr) = \psi_1\bigl(h(\gamma)\bigr)\text{ for }\gamma\in\Gamma^{\ne}. \]

If $\Gamma \subseteq \Gamma _1$ and the inclusion $\Gamma \hookrightarrow \Gamma _1$ is an embedding $(\Gamma,\,\psi ) \to (\Gamma _1,\,\psi _1)$, then we call $(\Gamma _1,\,\psi _1)$ an extension of $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$. If $(\Gamma _1,\, \psi _1)$ is of Hahn type and extends $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$, then $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$ is of Hahn type.

Embedding lemmas

The lemmas in this subsection are the analogues for $H$-couples over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ of similar lemmas for $H$-couples in [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2, § 9.8]. The proofs are essentially the same, so we omit them.

Lemma 2.1 Let $\beta$ be a gap in $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$. Then there is an $H$-couple ${(\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}} \alpha,\, \psi ^{\alpha })}$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ that extends $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ such that:

  1. (i) $\alpha >0$ and $\alpha '=\beta ;$

  2. (ii) if $i\colon (\Gamma,\,\psi )\to (\Gamma _1,\,\psi _1)$ is an embedding and $\alpha _1\in \Gamma _1,$ $\alpha _1>0,$ $\alpha _1'=i(\beta ),$ then $i$ extends uniquely to an embedding $j\colon \bigl (\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}} \alpha,\, \psi ^{\alpha }\bigr )\to (\Gamma _1,\,\psi _1)$ with $j(\alpha )=\alpha _1$.

The universal property (ii) determines $(\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\alpha,\, \psi ^{\alpha })$ up to isomorphism over $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$, and $0< c\alpha < \Gamma ^{>}$ for all $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}^{>}$; moreover, for all $\gamma \in \Gamma$ and $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}$ with $\gamma +c\alpha \ne 0$,

(1)\begin{equation} \psi^{\alpha}(\gamma+c \alpha) = \begin{cases} \psi(\gamma), & \text{if }\gamma\neq 0,\\ \beta-\alpha, & \text{otherwise.} \end{cases} \end{equation}

Note also that $[\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\alpha ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}} \cup \big \{[\alpha ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\big \}$, so for $\Psi ^{\alpha }:=\psi ^{\alpha }((\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\alpha )^{\ne })$ we have:

(2)\begin{equation} \Psi^{\alpha} = \Psi\cup\{\beta-\alpha\}, \quad \max\Psi^{\alpha} = \psi^{\alpha}(\alpha) = \beta-\alpha. \end{equation}

Lemma 2.1 goes through with $\alpha < 0$ and $\alpha _1 <0$ in place of $\alpha >0$ and $\alpha _1 > 0$, respectively. In the setting of this modified lemma, we have $\Gamma ^{<} < c\alpha < 0$ for all $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}^{>}$, (1) goes through for $\gamma \in \Gamma$ and $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}$ with $\gamma + c\alpha \ne 0$, (2) goes through. So we have two ways to remove a gap. Removal of a gap as above leads by (2) to a grounded $H$-couple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$, and this is the situation we consider next.

Lemma 2.2 Assume that $\Psi$ has a largest element $\beta$. Then there exists an $H$-couple ${(\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}} \alpha,\, \psi ^{\alpha })}$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ that extends $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ with $\alpha \ne 0,$ $\alpha '=\beta,$ such that for any embedding $i\colon (\Gamma,\,\psi )\to (\Gamma _1,\,\psi _1)$ and any $\alpha _1\in \Gamma _1^{\ne }$ with $\alpha _1'=i(\beta )$ there is a unique extension of $i$ to an embedding $j\colon (\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}} \alpha,\, \psi ^{\alpha })\to (\Gamma _1,\,\psi _1)$ with $j(\alpha )=\alpha _1$.

Let $(\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\alpha,\, \psi ^{\alpha })$ be as in Lemma 2.2. Then $\Gamma ^{<} < c\alpha < 0$ for all $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}^{>}$, $[\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\alpha ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}} \cup \big \{[\alpha ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\big \}$, so (2) holds for $\Psi ^{\alpha }:=\psi ^{\alpha }((\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\alpha )^{\ne })$. Thus, our new $\Psi$-set $\Psi ^{\alpha }$ still has a maximum, but this maximum is larger than the maximum $\beta$ of the original $\Psi$-set $\Psi$. By iterating this construction indefinitely and taking a union, we obtain an $H$-couple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ with asymptotic integration.

Once we have an $H$-couple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ with asymptotic integration, we can create an extension with a gap as follows:

Lemma 2.3 Suppose that $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$ has asymptotic integration. Then there is an $H$-couple $(\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta,\, \psi _{\beta })$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ extending $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$ such that:

  1. (i) $\Psi < \beta < (\Gamma ^{>})';$

  2. (ii) for any $(\Gamma _1,\, \psi _1)$ extending $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$ and $\beta _1\in \Gamma _1$ with $\Psi < \beta _1 < (\Gamma ^{>})'$ there is a unique embedding $(\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta,\, \psi _{\beta })\to (\Gamma _1,\, \psi _1)$ of $H$-couples over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ that is the identity on $\Gamma$ and sends $\beta$ to $\beta _1$.

Let $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$ and $(\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta,\, \psi _{\beta })$ be as in Lemma 2.3. If $(\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\alpha,\, \psi _{\alpha })$ is also an $H$-couple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ extending $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$ with $\Psi < \alpha < (\Gamma ^{>})'$, then by (ii) we have an isomorphism $(\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta,\, \psi _{\beta })\to (\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\alpha,\, \psi _{\alpha })$ of $H$-couples over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ that is the identity on $\Gamma$ and sends $\beta$ to $\alpha$. In this sense, $(\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta,\, \psi _{\beta })$ is unique up to isomorphism over $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$. The construction of $(\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta,\, \psi _{\beta })$ gives the following extra information, with $\Psi _{\beta }$ the set of values of $\psi _{\beta }$ on $(\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta )^{\ne }$:

Corollary 2.4 The set $\Gamma$ is dense in the ordered abelian group $\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta$, so $[\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}} = [\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}},$ $\Psi _{\beta }=\Psi$ and $\beta$ is a gap in $(\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta,\, \psi _{\beta })$.

Recall that a cut in an ordered set $S$ is just a downward closed subset of $S$, and that an element $a$ of an ordered set extending $S$ is said to realize a cut $D$ in $S$ if $D< a< S\setminus D$ (so $a\notin S$).

Lemma 2.5 Let $D$ be a cut in $[\Gamma ^{\ne }]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ and let $\beta \in \Gamma$ be such that $\beta <(\Gamma ^{>})'$, $\gamma ^{\dagger} \leqslant \beta$ for all $\gamma \in \Gamma ^{\ne }$ with $[\gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}> D$, and $\beta \leqslant \delta ^{\dagger}$ for all $\delta \in \Gamma ^{\ne }$ with $[\delta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\in D$. Then there exists an $H$-couple $(\Gamma \oplus {\boldsymbol {k}}\alpha,\,\psi ^\alpha )$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ that extends $(\Gamma,\,\psi ),$ with $\alpha >0,$ such that:

  1. (i) $[\alpha ]_{\boldsymbol {k}}$ realizes the cut $D$ in $[\Gamma ^{\ne }]_{\boldsymbol {k}},$ and $\psi ^\alpha (\alpha )=\beta ;$

  2. (ii) for any embedding $i\colon (\Gamma,\,\psi )\to (\Gamma _1,\,\psi _1)$ and $\alpha _1\in \Gamma _1^{>}$ such that $[\alpha _1]_{\boldsymbol {k}}$ realizes the cut $\bigl \{\bigl [i(\delta )\bigr ]_{\boldsymbol {k}}: [\delta ]_{\boldsymbol {k}}\in D\bigr \}$ in $\bigl [i(\Gamma ^{\ne })\bigr ]_{\boldsymbol {k}}$ and $\psi _1(\alpha _1)=i(\beta ),$ $i$ extends uniquely to an embedding $j\colon {(\Gamma \oplus {\boldsymbol {k}}\alpha,\,\psi ^\alpha )}\to (\Gamma _1,\,\psi _1)$ with $j(\alpha )= \alpha _1$.

Moreover, $[\Gamma \oplus {\boldsymbol {k}}\alpha ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}} \cup \big \{[\alpha ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\big \}$ and $\Psi ^{\alpha }:=\psi ^{\alpha }((\Gamma \oplus {\boldsymbol {k}}\alpha )^{\ne })=\Psi \cup \{\beta \}$. If $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$ is grounded, then so is $(\Gamma \oplus {\boldsymbol {k}}\alpha,\, \psi ^\alpha )$. If $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ has asymptotic integration, then so does $(\Gamma \oplus {\boldsymbol {k}}\alpha,\, \psi ^\alpha )$. If $\beta \in \Psi ^{\downarrow }$, then a gap in $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ remains a gap in $(\Gamma \oplus {\boldsymbol {k}}\alpha,\, \psi ^{\alpha })$.

Proof. By a straightforward analogue of [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2, Lemma 2.4.5] we extend $\Gamma$ to an ordered vector space $\Gamma ^{\alpha }=\Gamma \oplus {\boldsymbol {k}}\alpha$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ with $\alpha >0$ such that $[\alpha ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ realizes the cut $D$ in $[\Gamma ^{\ne }]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. Then $[\Gamma \oplus {\boldsymbol {k}}\alpha ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}} \cup \big \{[\alpha ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\big \}$. We extend $\psi$ to $\psi ^{\alpha }\colon (\Gamma ^{\alpha })^{\ne } \to \Gamma$ by

\[ \psi^{\alpha}(\gamma+c\alpha) := \min\!\big\{\psi(\gamma),\beta\big\}\ \text{ for }\gamma\in \Gamma, c\in {\boldsymbol{k}}^\times. \]

Apart from some obvious changes, we now follow the proof of [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2, Lemma 9.8.7]. This gives the desired results, except for the last Claim of the lemma. To prove that claim, let $\beta \in \Psi ^{\downarrow }$, let $\gamma \in \Gamma$ be a gap in $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$, and assume towards a contradiction that $\gamma$ is not a gap in $(\Gamma ^{\alpha },\,\psi ^{\alpha })$. Then $\gamma > \Psi ^\alpha$, so $\gamma =(\delta +c\alpha )'$ with $\delta \in \Gamma$, $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}^\times$ and $0 <\delta +c\alpha < \Gamma ^{>}$. Then $[\delta +c\alpha ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\notin [\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$, so $[\delta +c\alpha ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\alpha ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. As $\Psi$ has no largest element, we get $\Psi < (\delta +c\alpha )^{\dagger} =\alpha ^{\dagger} =\beta$, a contradiction.

The case of Hahn type

In Lemma 2.1 (and in its variant with $\alpha <0$), in Lemma 2.2, and in Lemma 2.5 for $\beta \notin \Psi$, we have:

\[ \text{ if }(\Gamma, \psi)\text{ is of Hahn type, then so is }(\Gamma+{\boldsymbol{k}}\alpha, \psi^{\alpha}). \]

Suppose $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$ and $(\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta,\, \psi _{\beta })$ are as in Lemma 2.3, and $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ is of Hahn type. We claim that then $(\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta,\, \psi _{\beta })$ is also of Hahn type. To prove this claim, recall from Corollary 2.4 that $\Gamma$ is dense in $\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta$. It follows easily that for non-zero $\alpha _1,\, \alpha _2\in \Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta$ with $\psi _{\beta }(\alpha _1)=\psi _{\beta }(\alpha _2)$ we have $[\alpha _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\alpha _2]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. It remains to show that $\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta$ is a Hahn space over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$. So let $\alpha _1,\, \alpha _2\in \Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta$ be non-zero with $[\alpha _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\alpha _2]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. By density again, and the fact that $[\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ has no least element $> [0]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$, we have $\gamma _1,\, \gamma _2\in \Gamma$ such that $[\alpha _1-\gamma _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}< [\alpha _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ and $[\alpha _2-\gamma _2]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}< [\alpha _2]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. Take $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}^\times$ such that $[\gamma _1-c\gamma _2]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}< [\gamma _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. It follows easily that then $[\alpha _1-c\alpha _2]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}< [\alpha _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$.

New extension lemmas

The three next lemmas will enable in the next section a simpler proof of QE for closed $H$-couples than in [Reference Aschenbrenner and van den Dries1]: in that paper, we needed “properties (A) and (B)” with long and tedious proofs, and here we avoid this.

Lemma 2.6 Suppose $(\Gamma _1,\,\psi _1)$ extends $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$. Let $\beta \in \Gamma _1\setminus \Gamma$ and $\alpha _0\in \Gamma$ be such that $(\beta -\alpha _0)^{\dagger} \notin \Gamma$. Then $(\beta -\alpha _0)^{\dagger} = \max \big \{(\beta -\alpha )^{\dagger} :\,\alpha \in \Gamma \big \}$. If in addition $\Gamma ^{<}$ is cofinal in $\Gamma _1^{<},$ then $(\beta -\alpha _0)^{\dagger} \leqslant \text { some element of }\Psi$.

Proof. Suppose $\alpha \in \Gamma$ and $(\beta -\alpha )^{\dagger} > (\beta -\alpha _0)^{\dagger}$. Then $\alpha -\alpha _0=(\beta -\alpha _0)-(\beta -\alpha )$ gives $(\beta -\alpha _0)^{\dagger} =(\alpha -\alpha _0)^{\dagger} \in \Gamma$, a contradiction. Assume $|\beta -\alpha _0|\geqslant |\gamma |$, $\gamma \in \Gamma ^{\ne }$. Then $(\beta -\alpha _0)^{\dagger} \leqslant \gamma ^{\dagger} \in \Psi$.

Lemma 2.7 Suppose $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ is closed and $(\Gamma _1,\, \psi _1)$ and $(\Gamma _*,\,\psi _*)$ are $H$-couples over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ extending $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$. Let $\beta \in \Gamma _1\setminus \Gamma$ and $\beta _*\in \Gamma _*\setminus \Gamma$ realize the same cut in $\Gamma$, and suppose that $\beta ^{\dagger} \notin \Gamma$ and $\Gamma ^{<}$ are cofinal in $(\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta ^{\dagger} )^{<}$. Then $\beta _*^{\dagger} \notin \Gamma,$ and $\beta ^{\dagger}$ and $\beta _*^{\dagger}$ realize the same cut in $\Gamma$.

Proof. Let $\alpha \in \Gamma ^{\ne }$. We claim:

\[ \beta^{\dagger}{<}\alpha^{\dagger}\ \Rightarrow\ \beta_*^{\dagger}{<}\alpha^{\dagger}, \quad \beta^{\dagger}{>}\alpha^{\dagger}\ \Rightarrow\ \beta_*^{\dagger}{>}\alpha^{\dagger}. \]

To prove the first implication, assume $\beta ^{\dagger} <\alpha ^{\dagger}$. Then $|\beta |>|\alpha |$, so $|\beta _*|>|\alpha |$, and thus $\beta _*^{\dagger} \leqslant \alpha ^{\dagger}$. Since $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ is closed and $\Gamma ^{<}$ is cofinal in $(\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta ^{\dagger} )^{<}$, we can replace in this argument $\alpha$ by some $\gamma \in \Gamma ^{\ne }$ with $\beta ^{\dagger} <\gamma ^{\dagger} <\alpha ^{\dagger}$, to get $\beta _*^{\dagger} \leqslant \gamma ^{\dagger} <\alpha ^{\dagger}$, and thus $\beta _*^{\dagger} <\alpha ^{\dagger}$ as claimed. The second implication follows in the same way.

If $\beta ^{\dagger} < \gamma ^{\dagger}$ for some $\gamma \in \Gamma ^{\ne }$, then $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ being closed gives the desired conclusion. If $\beta ^{\dagger} >\Psi$, then we use instead $\Psi < \beta ^{\dagger} < (\Gamma ^{>})'$ and $\Psi < \beta _*^{\dagger} < (\Gamma ^{>})'$.

Lemma 2.8 Suppose $(\Gamma _1,\,\psi _1)$ extends $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$. Let $\beta \in \Gamma _1\setminus \Gamma$ and $\alpha _0,\, \alpha _1\in \Gamma$ be such that $\beta _0^{\dagger} \notin \Gamma$ for $\beta _0:= \beta -\alpha _0$ and $\beta _1^{\dagger} \notin \Psi$ for $\beta _1:=\beta _0^{\dagger} -\alpha _1$. Assume also that $|\beta _0|\geqslant |\alpha |$ for some $\alpha \in \Gamma ^{\ne }$. Then $\beta _0^{\dagger} < \beta _1^{\dagger}$.

Proof. From $|\beta _0|\geqslant |\alpha |$ with $\alpha \in \Gamma ^{\ne }$ we get $\beta _0^{\dagger} \leqslant \alpha ^{\dagger}$. Also, $\beta _0^{\dagger} -\alpha ^{\dagger} \notin \Gamma$ and ${[\beta _0^{\dagger} -\alpha _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}}\notin [\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$, hence $[\beta _0^{\dagger} -\alpha ^{\dagger} ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\geqslant [\beta _0^{\dagger} -\alpha _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. In view of [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2, 6.5.4(i)], this gives

\[ \beta_0^{\dagger}{=} \min(\beta_0^{\dagger},\alpha^{\dagger}) < (\beta_0^{\dagger}{-}\alpha^{\dagger})^{\dagger}\ \leqslant\ (\beta_0^{\dagger}{-}\alpha_1)^{\dagger}{=} \beta_1^{\dagger}. \]

3. Eliminating quantifiers for closed $H$-couples

Eliminating quantifiers for closed $H$-couples requires a predicate for their $\Psi$-set, and in this connection, we need to study the substructures of the thus expanded $H$-couples. Accordingly, we define an $H$-triple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ to be a triple $(\Gamma,\, \psi,\, P)$ where $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ is an $H$-couple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ and $P\subseteq \Gamma$ is an $H$-cut in $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$.

Lemma 3.1 Let $(\Gamma,\,\psi,\, P)$ be an $H$-triple over ${\boldsymbol {k}},$ and let $\beta \in P\setminus \Psi$. Then $(\Gamma,\,\psi,\, P)$ can be extended to an $H$-triple $(\Gamma \oplus {\boldsymbol {k}}\alpha,\, \psi ^{\alpha },\, P^{\alpha })$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ such that:

  1. (i) $\alpha >0$ and $\psi ^{\alpha }(\alpha )=\beta ;$

  2. (ii) given any embedding $i\colon (\Gamma,\, \psi,\, P)\to (\Gamma ^*,\, \psi ^*,\, P^*)$ and any element $\alpha ^*>0$ in $\Gamma ^*$ with $\psi ^*(\alpha ^*)=i(\beta )$, there is a unique extension of $i$ to an embedding $j\colon (\Gamma \oplus {\boldsymbol {k}}\alpha,\, \psi ^{\alpha },\, P^{\alpha })\to (\Gamma ^*,\, \psi ^*,\, P^*)$ with $j(\alpha )=\alpha ^*$.

If $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ is of Hahn type, then so is $(\Gamma \oplus {\boldsymbol {k}}\alpha,\, \psi ^{\alpha })$.

Proof. Distinguishing various cases this follows from Lemma 2.5, especially the claims beginning with “Moreover”. Use also “The case of Hahn type”.

An $H$-closure of an $H$-triple $(\Gamma,\, \psi,\, P)$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ is defined to be a closed $H$-triple $(\Gamma ^{\operatorname {c}},\, \psi ^{\operatorname {c}},\, P^{\operatorname {c}})$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ that extends $(\Gamma,\,\psi,\,P)$ such that any embedding

\[ (\Gamma, \psi, P)\ \to\ (\Gamma^*, \psi^*, P^*) \]

into a closed $H$-triple $(\Gamma ^*,\, \psi ^*,\, P^*)$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ extends to an embedding

\[ (\Gamma^{\operatorname{c}}, \psi^{\operatorname{c}}, P^{\operatorname{c}})\ \to\ (\Gamma^*, \psi^*, P^*). \]

Corollary 3.2 Every $H$-triple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ has an $H$-closure. Every $H$-triple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ of Hahn type has an $H$-closure that is of Hahn type.

Proof. This is a straightforward consequence of Lemmas 2.1, 2.2, and 3.1, using for the second statement also the remarks in “The case of Hahn type”.

We consider $H$-triples as $\mathcal {L}_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$-structures where $\mathcal {L}_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ is the natural language of ordered vector spaces over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$, augmented by a constant symbol $\infty$, a unary function symbol $\psi$, and a unary relation symbol $P$. The underlying set of an $H$-triple $(\Gamma,\, \psi,\, P)$, when construed as an $\mathcal {L}_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$-structure, is $\Gamma _{\infty }$ rather than $\Gamma$, and the symbols of $\mathcal {L}_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ are interpreted in $(\Gamma,\, \psi,\, P)$ as usual, with $\infty$ serving as a default value:

\[ \psi(0) = \psi(\infty) = \gamma+\infty = \infty+\gamma = \infty + \infty ={-}\infty = c\infty = \infty \]

for $\gamma \in \Gamma$ and $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}$. Also $0^{\dagger} :=\infty$ for the zero element $0\in \Gamma$, so $\Gamma ^{\dagger} =\Psi \cup \{\infty \}$.

Theorem 3.3 The $\mathcal {L}_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$-theory of closed $H$-triples over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ has $\operatorname {QE}$.

The proof of QE

Towards Theorem 3.3 we consider an $H$-triple $(\Gamma,\, \psi,\, P)$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ and closed $H$-triples $(\Gamma _1,\, \psi _1,\, P_1)$ and $(\Gamma _*,\, \psi _*,\, P_*)$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ that extend $(\Gamma,\, \psi,\, P)$, and such that $(\Gamma _*,\, \psi _*,\, P_*)$ is $|\Gamma |^+$-saturated. For $\gamma \in \Gamma _1$ we let $(\Gamma \langle \gamma \rangle,\, \psi _{\gamma })$ be the $H$-couple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ generated by $\Gamma \cup \{\gamma \}$ in $(\Gamma _1,\, \psi _1)$, and set $P_{\gamma }:= P_1\cap \Gamma \langle \gamma \rangle$.

Let $\beta \in \Gamma _1\setminus \Gamma$. Theorem 3.3 follows if we can show that under these assumptions $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\,\psi _{\beta },\, P_{\beta })$ can be embedded over $\Gamma$ into $(\Gamma _*,\, \psi _*,\, P_*)$. We first do this in a situation that may seem rather special:

Lemma 3.4 Suppose $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$ has asymptotic integration and $(\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta )^{\dagger} =\Gamma ^{\dagger}$. Then $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\,\psi _{\beta },\, P_{\beta })$ can be embedded over $\Gamma$ into $(\Gamma _*,\, \psi _*,\, P_*)$.

Proof. From $(\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta )^{\dagger} =\Gamma ^{\dagger}$ we get $\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle =\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta$. We have six cases:

Case 1: $(\Gamma ^{>})^{\dagger} < \eta < (\Gamma ^{>})'$ and $\eta \in P_1$ for some $\eta \in \Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta$. Fix such $\eta$. Then $\Gamma$ is dense in $\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\eta =\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta$, by Corollary 2.4, so $[\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. Moreover, there is no $\eta _1\ne \eta$ in $\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta$ with $(\Gamma ^{>})^{\dagger} < \eta _1 < (\Gamma ^{>})'$. By saturation, we can take $\eta _*\in \Gamma _*$ such that $(\Gamma ^{>})^{\dagger} < \eta _* < (\Gamma ^{>})'$ and $\eta _*\in P_*$. Then [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2, 2.4.16] yields an embedding $i \colon \Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta \to \Gamma _*$ of ordered vector spaces over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ that is the identity on $\Gamma$ with $i(\eta )=\eta _*$. This $i$ embeds $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\,\psi _{\beta },\, P_{\beta })$ into $(\Gamma _*,\, \psi _*,\, P_*)$.

Case 2: $(\Gamma ^{>})^{\dagger} < \eta < (\Gamma ^{>})'$ and $\eta \notin P_1$ for some $\eta \in \Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta$. Fixing such $\eta$, we repeat the argument of Case 1, except that now $\eta _*\notin P_*$ instead of $\eta _*\in P_*$.

Case 3: $[\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$, but there is no $\eta \in \Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta$ with $(\Gamma ^{>})^{\dagger} < \eta < (\Gamma ^{>})'$. Then $P_{\beta }$ is the only $H$-cut of $\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle$. Saturation yields $\beta _*\in \Gamma _*$ realizing the same cut in $\Gamma$ as $\beta$. Then [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2, 2.4.16] yields an embedding $i \colon \Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta \to \Gamma _*$ of ordered vector spaces over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ that is the identity on $\Gamma$ with $i(\beta )=\beta _*$. For $\gamma \in \Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta$ we have $[i(\gamma )]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\in [\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$, so $i(\gamma )^{\dagger} =\gamma ^{\dagger} \in \Gamma ^{\dagger}$. Thus, $i$ embeds $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\,\psi _{\beta },\, P_{\beta })$ into $(\Gamma _*,\, \psi _*,\, P_*)$.

Assume next that we are not in Case 1, or Case 2, or Case 3. Then $[\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\ne [\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. Take $\gamma \in \Gamma \langle \beta \rangle \setminus \Gamma$ such that $\gamma >0$ and $[\gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\notin [\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$, so $[\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}} \cup \big \{[\gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\big \}$. We are not in Case 1 or Case 2, so $P_{\beta }$ is the only $H$-cut of $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\, \psi _{\beta })$. Let $D$ be the cut in $\Gamma$ realized by $\gamma$ and $E:= \Gamma \setminus D$, so $D<\gamma < E$. Then $D$ has no largest element, and so $D\cap \Gamma ^{>}\ne \emptyset$: if $d=\max D$, then we have $0 <\gamma -d< \Gamma ^{>}$, and thus $(\Gamma ^{>})^{\dagger} < (\gamma -d)^{\dagger} < (\Gamma ^{>})'$, contradicting that we are not in Case 1. Likewise, $E$ has no least element. Here are the remaining cases:

Case 4: $\gamma ^{\dagger} \in (D^{>0})^{\dagger} \cap E^{\dagger}$. Saturation yields $\gamma _*\in \Gamma _*$ realizing the same cut in $\Gamma$ as $\gamma$. Then $\gamma _*^{\dagger} =\gamma ^{\dagger} \in (D^{>0})^{\dagger}$, and [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2, 2.4.16] yields an embedding $i \colon \Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta \to \Gamma _*$ of ordered vector spaces over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ that is the identity on $\Gamma$ with $i(\gamma )=\gamma _*$; this $i$ embeds $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\,\psi _{\beta },\, P_{\beta })$ into $(\Gamma _*,\, \psi _*,\, P_*)$.

Case 5: $\gamma ^{\dagger} \in (D^{>0})^{\dagger} > E^{\dagger}$. Then saturation yields a $\gamma _*\in \Gamma _{*}$ realizing the same cut in $\Gamma$ as $\gamma$, with $\gamma _*^{\dagger} =\gamma ^{\dagger}$. By [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2, 2.4.16] this yields an embedding $i \colon \Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta \to \Gamma _*$ of ordered vector spaces over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ that is the identity on $\Gamma$ with $i(\gamma )=\gamma _*$, and so as before $i$ embeds $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\, \psi _{\beta },\, P_{\beta })$ into $(\Gamma _*,\, \psi _*,\, P_*)$.

Case 6: $\gamma ^{\dagger} \in E^{\dagger} < (D^{>0})^{\dagger}$. This is handled just like Case 5.

Note that Cases 4, 5, 6 in the proof above do not occur if $(\Gamma _1,\,\psi _1)$ is of Hahn type.

In view of Corollary 3.2 and Lemma 3.4, Theorem 3.3 reduces to:

Lemma 3.5 Suppose $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ is closed and $(\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\gamma )^{\dagger} \ne \Gamma ^{\dagger}$ for all $\gamma \in \Gamma _1\setminus \Gamma$. Then $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\, \psi _{\beta },\, P_{\beta })$ embeds into $(\Gamma _*,\, \psi _*,\, P_*)$ over $\Gamma$.

Proof. If $\gamma \in \Gamma _1\setminus \Gamma$ and $\Psi < \gamma < (\Gamma ^{>})'$, then $(\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\gamma )^{\dagger} = \Gamma ^{\dagger}$, contradicting our assumption. Hence there is no such $\gamma$. It follows that $\Gamma ^{<}$ is cofinal in $\Gamma _1^{<}$.

Take $\alpha _0\in \Gamma$ such that $(\beta -\alpha _0)^{\dagger} \notin \Gamma ^{\dagger}$. Since $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ is closed, this means ${(\beta -\alpha _0)^{\dagger} \notin \Gamma }$. Next take $\alpha _1\in \Gamma$ with $((\beta -\alpha _0)^{\dagger} -\alpha _1)^{\dagger} \notin \Gamma ^{\dagger}$. Continuing this way, we obtain sequences $\alpha _0,\, \alpha _1,\, \alpha _2,\,\ldots$ in $\Gamma$ and $\beta _0,\, \beta _1,\, \beta _2,\,\ldots$ in $\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle \setminus \Gamma$ with

\[ \beta_0 = \beta-\alpha_0, \qquad \beta_{n+1} = \beta_{n}^{\dagger}{-}\alpha_{n+1} \text{ for all }n, \]

such that $\beta _n^{\dagger} \notin \Gamma$ for all $n$. By Lemma 2.8 we have $\beta _0^{\dagger} < \beta _1^{\dagger} < \beta _2^{\dagger} < \cdots$. It follows that $[\beta _0]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}} >[\beta _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}} >[\beta _2]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}} > \cdots$, with $[\beta _n]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\notin [\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ for all $n$. In particular, the family $(\beta _n)$ is ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-linearly independent over $\Gamma$, and

\[ \Gamma\langle\beta\rangle = \Gamma\oplus {\boldsymbol{k}}\beta_0 \oplus {\boldsymbol{k}}\beta_1 \oplus {\boldsymbol{k}}\beta_2\oplus \cdots. \]

By saturation we can take $\beta _*\in \Gamma _*\setminus \Gamma$ realizing the same cut in $\Gamma$ as $\beta$. This gives an embedding $e_0\colon \Gamma \oplus {\boldsymbol {k}} \beta \to \Gamma _*$ of ordered vector spaces over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ that is the identity on $\Gamma$ and sends $\beta$ to $\beta _*$. We define recursively $\beta _{*n}\in (\Gamma _*)_\infty$ by

\[ \beta_{*0}:= \beta_*-\alpha_0, \qquad \beta_{*(n+1)} := \beta_{*n}^{\dagger}{-}\alpha_{n+1}. \]

Assume inductively that $\beta _{*0},\,\ldots,\,\beta _{*n}\in \Gamma _{*}$ and that we have an embedding

\[ e_n\ :\ \Gamma+{\boldsymbol{k}}\beta_0+ \cdots + {\boldsymbol{k}}\beta_n \to \Gamma_{*} \]

of ordered vector spaces over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ that is the identity on $\Gamma$ and sends $\beta _i$ to $\beta _{*i}$ for $i=0,\,\ldots,\,n$. Then $\beta _n$ and $\beta _{*n}$ realize the same cut in $\Gamma$, and so $\beta _{*n}^{\dagger} \notin \Gamma$, and $\beta _n^{\dagger}$ and $\beta _{*n}^{\dagger}$ realize the same cut in $\Gamma$ by Lemma 2.7. Hence $\beta _{n+1}$ and $\beta _{*(n+1)}\in \Gamma _*\setminus \Gamma$ realize the same cut in $\Gamma$. Moreover, $\beta ^{\dagger} _{*n} < \beta _{*(n+1)}^{\dagger}$ by Lemma 2.8. We have

\[ [\Gamma+{\boldsymbol{k}}\beta_0+\cdots +{\boldsymbol{k}}\beta_n]_{{\boldsymbol{k}}} = [\Gamma]_{{\boldsymbol{k}}}\cup\big\{[\beta_0]_{{\boldsymbol{k}}},\ldots,[\beta_n]_{{\boldsymbol{k}}}\big\},\quad [\beta_0]_{{\boldsymbol{k}}} >\cdots >[\beta_n]_{{\boldsymbol{k}}} > [\beta_{n+1}]_{{\boldsymbol{k}}}. \]

Let $D$ be the cut realized by $[\beta _{n+1}]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ in $[\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _0+\cdots +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _n]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. Then the above together with $[\beta _{*n}]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}} > [\beta _{*(n+1)}]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ shows that $[\beta _{*(n+1)}]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ realizes the $e_n$-image of the cut $D$ in $[e_n(\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _0+\cdots +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _n)]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. Hence $e_n$ extends to an embedding

\[ e_{n+1}\ :\ \Gamma+{\boldsymbol{k}}\beta_1+ \cdots + {\boldsymbol{k}}\beta_n+{\boldsymbol{k}}\beta_{n+1} \to \Gamma_{*} \]

of ordered vector spaces over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ that is the identity on $\Gamma$ and sends $\beta _{n+1}$ to $\beta _{*(n+1)}$. This leads to a map $e\colon \Gamma \langle \beta \rangle \to \Gamma _*$ that extends each $e_n$, and is, therefore, an embedding of $H$-couples over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$. Since $P_{\beta }$ is the only $H$-cut in $\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle$, $e$ embeds $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\, \psi _{\beta },\, P_{\beta })$ into $(\Gamma _*,\, \psi _*,\, P_*)$ over $\Gamma$.

This concludes the proof of Theorem 3.3.

Let $T_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ be the $\mathcal {L}_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$-theory of closed $H$-triples over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$. Let $T_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}^{>}$ be the $\mathcal {L}_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$-theory whose models are the closed $H$-triples $(\Gamma,\,\psi,\, P)$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ with $0\in P$, equivalently $\Psi \cap \Gamma ^{>}\ne \emptyset$. Let $T_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}^{<}$ be the $\mathcal {L}_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$-theory whose models are the closed $H$-triples $(\Gamma,\,\psi,\, P)$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ with $0\notin P$, equivalently $\Psi \subseteq \Gamma ^{<}$.

Corollary 3.6 The $\mathcal {L}_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$-theory $T_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ has exactly two completions: $T_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}^{>}$ and $T_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}^{<}$.

Proof. We have an $H$-triple $(\{0\},\,\psi _0,\, \{0\})$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ that embeds into every model of $T_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}^{>}$, and an $H$-triple $(\{0\},\,\psi _0,\, \emptyset )$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ that embeds into every model of $T_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}^{<}$. Here $\psi _0$ is the “empty” function $\emptyset \to \{0\}$.

Suppose $K$ is a Liouville closed $H$-field. Then its $H$-couple $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ is naturally an $H$-couple over its constant field $C$. The case $(\Gamma,\,\psi )\models T_{C}^{>}$ corresponds to the derivation $\partial$ of $K$ being small (that is, $\partial f \prec 1$ for all $f\prec 1$ in $K$), while the case $(\Gamma,\,\psi )\models T_{C}^{<}$ corresponds to this derivation not being small. For example, the usual derivation $\frac {d}{dx}$ of $\mathbb {T}$ is small. The derivation $x^2\frac {d}{dx}$ on $\mathbb {T}$ is not small, but $\mathbb {T}$ with this derivation is still Liouville closed.

4. Simple extensions

Let $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$ be an $H$-couple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ with asymptotic integration, and let $(\Gamma ^*,\, \psi ^*)$ be an $H$-couple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ that extends $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$. For $\gamma \in \Gamma ^*$, let $(\Gamma \langle \gamma \rangle,\,\psi _\gamma )$ denote the $H$-couple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ generated by $\Gamma \cup \{\gamma \}$ in $(\Gamma ^*,\, \psi ^*)$. Let $\beta \in \Gamma ^*\setminus \Gamma$. The following result yields a useful description of the “simple” extension $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\,\psi _\beta )$, where $i$, $n$ range over $\mathbb {N}=\{0,\,1,\,2,\,\ldots \}$:

Proposition 4.1 One of the following occurs:

  1. (a) $(\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta )^{\dagger} =\Gamma ^{\dagger} ;$

  2. (b) there are sequences $(\alpha _i)$ in $\Gamma$ and $(\beta _i)$ in $\Gamma ^*$ such that $(\beta _i)$ is ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-linearly independent over $\Gamma,$ $\beta _0=\beta -\alpha _0$ and $\beta _{i+1}=\beta _i^{\dagger} -\alpha _{i+1}$ for all $i$, and such that $\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle =\Gamma \oplus \bigoplus _{i=0}^\infty {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _i$.

  3. (c) n there are $\alpha _0,\,\ldots,\,\alpha _n\in \Gamma,$ and non-zero $\beta _0,\,\ldots,\, \beta _n\in \Gamma ^*$ such that $\beta _0=\beta -\alpha _0,$ $\beta _{i+1}=\beta _i^{\dagger} -\alpha _{i+1}$ for $i< n,$ the vectors $\beta _0,\,\ldots,\, \beta _n,\, \beta _n^{\dagger}$ are ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-linearly independent over $\Gamma,$ $(\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _n^{\dagger} )^{\dagger} =\Gamma ^{\dagger},$ and $\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle =\Gamma \oplus \bigoplus _{i=0}^n {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _i \oplus {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _n^{\dagger}$.

  4. (d) n there are $\alpha _0,\,\ldots,\,\alpha _n\in \Gamma,$ and non-zero $\beta _0,\,\ldots,\, \beta _n\in \Gamma ^*$ such that $\beta _0=\beta -\alpha _0,$ $\beta _{i+1}=\beta _i^{\dagger} -\alpha _{i+1}$ for $i< n,$ the vectors $\beta _0,\,\ldots,\, \beta _n$ are ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-linearly independent over $\Gamma,$ $\beta _n^{\dagger} \in \Gamma \setminus \Gamma ^{\dagger},$ and $\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle =\Gamma \oplus \bigoplus _{i=0}^n {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _i$.

Note that in case (a) we have $\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle =\Gamma \oplus {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta$, a case described in more detail in Lemma 3.4. The proof below gives extra information about the other cases.

Proof. Suppose we are not in case (a). Then we have $\alpha _0\in \Gamma$ and $\beta _0:=\beta -\alpha _0$ with $\beta _0^{\dagger} \notin \Gamma ^{\dagger}$. This is the first step in inductively constructing elements $\alpha _i\in \Gamma$ and $\beta _i\in \Gamma \langle \beta \rangle \setminus \Gamma _0$, either for all $i$, or for all $i\leqslant n$ for a certain $n$. Suppose we already have $\alpha _0,\,\ldots,\, \alpha _n\in \Gamma$ and $\beta _0,\,\ldots,\, \beta _n\in \Gamma \langle \beta \rangle \setminus \Gamma$ with $\alpha _0$ and $\beta _0$ as above, $\beta _{i+1}=\beta _i^{\dagger} -\alpha _{i+1}$ and $\beta _i^{\dagger} \notin \Gamma$ for $i < n$, and $\beta _n^{\dagger} \notin \Gamma ^{\dagger}$. Thus, $[\beta _i]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\notin [\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ for $i\leqslant n$.

Claim 1$\beta _0^{\dagger} < \cdots < \beta _n^{\dagger}$.

Claim 2: there is no $\eta \in \Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}} \beta _0+ \cdots + {\boldsymbol {k}} \beta _n$ with $\Psi < \eta < (\Gamma ^{>})'$.

To prove Claim 1, assume towards a contradiction that $\beta _i^{\dagger} \geqslant \beta _{i+1}^{\dagger}$, $i< n$. Then by Lemma 2.8 we have $0<|\beta _i|<\Gamma ^{>}$, so $\Psi < \beta _i^{\dagger} < (\Gamma ^{>})'$, and thus $[\beta _{i+1}]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\in [\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ by Corollary 2.4, a contradiction. It follows from Claim 1 that $[\beta _0]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}} > \cdots > [\beta _n]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ and that $\beta _0,\,\ldots,\, \beta _n$ are ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-linearly independent over $\Gamma$. As to Claim 2, suppose towards a contradiction that $\Psi < \gamma + \delta < (\Gamma ^{>})'$ where $\gamma \in \Gamma$, $\delta \in {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _0+\cdots + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _n$. Then $\delta \ne 0$, and so $[\delta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\notin [\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. With $D:= \Psi -\gamma$ and $E:=(\Gamma ^{>})'-\gamma$, we have $D < \delta < E$. On the other hand, for every $\varepsilon \in \Gamma ^{>}$ there are $d\in D$ and $e\in E$ with $e-d<\varepsilon$, so $\Gamma$ is dense in $\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\delta$ by [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2, 2.4.17], contradicting $[\delta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\notin [\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. This concludes the proof of Claim 2.

If $(\beta _n^{\dagger} -\alpha _{n+1})^{\dagger} \notin \Gamma ^{\dagger}$ for some $\alpha _{n+1}\in \Gamma$ (so $\beta _n^{\dagger} \notin \Gamma$), then we take such an $\alpha _{n+1}$ and set $\beta _{n+1}:=\beta _n^{\dagger} -\alpha _{n+1}$. If there is no such $\alpha _{n+1}$, then the construction breaks off, with $\alpha _n$ and $\beta _n$ as the last vectors.

Suppose the construction goes on indefinitely. Then it yields infinite sequences $(\alpha _i)$ and $(\beta _i)$ as in case (b), in particular, $\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle =\Gamma \oplus \bigoplus _{i=0}^\infty {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _i$,

\[ \Psi_{\beta}\ :=\ \psi^*\big(\Gamma\langle\beta\rangle^{\ne}\big) = \Psi\cup\big\{\beta_i^{\dagger}:\,i\in \mathbb{N}\big\}, \]

and $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\, \psi _\beta )$ has asymptotic integration by Claim 2.

Next, assume that the construction stops with $\alpha _n$ and $\beta _n$ as the last vectors. Thus, $({\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _n^{\dagger} })^{\dagger} =\Gamma ^{\dagger}$. We have two cases:

Case 1: $\beta _n^{\dagger} \notin \Gamma$. Then $\alpha _0,\,\ldots,\, \alpha _n,\, \beta _0,\,\ldots,\, \beta _n$ are as in case (c)$_n$. Here is why. Set $\Delta :=\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _n^{\dagger}$, so $\Delta ^{{\dagger} }=\Gamma ^{\dagger}$. From $\beta _i^{\dagger} \notin \Delta ^{\dagger}$ for all $i\leqslant n$ and Claim 1 we obtain that $\beta _0,\,\ldots,\, \beta _n$ are ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-linearly independent over $\Delta$, with

\[ (\Delta + {\boldsymbol{k}}\beta_0+\cdots + {\boldsymbol{k}}\beta_n)^{\dagger}\ \subseteq\ \Delta + {\boldsymbol{k}}\beta_0+\cdots + {\boldsymbol{k}}\beta_n, \]

and $\beta \in \Delta + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _0$, which proves the assertion.

Case 2: $\beta _n^{\dagger} \in \Gamma$. Then $\alpha _0,\,\ldots,\, \alpha _n,\, \beta _0,\,\ldots,\, \beta _n$ are as in case (d)$_n$. Here is why. From $\beta _i^{\dagger} \notin \Gamma ^{\dagger}$ for all $i\leqslant n$ and Claim 1 we obtain that $\beta _0,\,\ldots,\, \beta _n$ are ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-linearly independent over $\Gamma$, with

\[ (\Gamma + {\boldsymbol{k}}\beta_0+\cdots + {\boldsymbol{k}}\beta_n)^{\dagger}\ \subseteq\ \Gamma + {\boldsymbol{k}}\beta_0+\cdots + {\boldsymbol{k}}\beta_n, \]

and $\beta \in \Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _0$, which proves the assertion.

In case (d)$_n$ we have $\beta _n^{\dagger} \in \Gamma \setminus \Gamma ^{\dagger}$, and this cannot happen if $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ is closed. The proof of Proposition 4.1 yields some further results that are needed later:

Lemma 4.2 Let $(\alpha _i)$ and $(\beta _i)$ be as in ${\rm (b)}$. Then:

  1. (i) $\beta _i^{\dagger} \notin \Gamma$ for all $i,$ and thus $[\beta _i]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\notin [\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ for all $i;$

  2. (ii) $(\beta _i^{\dagger} )$ is strictly increasing, and thus $([\beta _i]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}})$ is strictly decreasing;

  3. (iii) $[\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\cup \big \{[\beta _i]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}:\,i\in \mathbb {N}\big \},$ and thus $\Psi _{\beta } = \Psi \cup \big \{\beta _i^{\dagger} :\, i\in \mathbb {N}\big \};$

  4. (iv) there is no $\eta \in \Gamma \langle \beta \rangle$ with $\Psi < \eta < (\Gamma ^{>})';$

  5. (v) $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\, \psi _\beta )$ has asymptotic integration;

  6. (vi) $\Gamma ^{<}$ is cofinal in $\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle ^{<}$.

If $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$ is closed and $\gamma \in \Gamma ^*\setminus \Gamma$ realizes the same cut in $\Gamma$ as $\beta$, then we have an isomorphism $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\, \psi _{\beta })\to (\Gamma \langle \gamma \rangle,\, \psi _{\gamma })$ of $H$-couples over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ that is the identity on $\Gamma$ and sends $\beta$ to $\gamma$. If $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$ is of Hahn type, then so is $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\, \psi _{\beta })$.

Proof. As to (i), this follows from the ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-linear independence of $(\beta _i)$ over $\Gamma$ and from $\beta _{i}^{\dagger} =\beta _{i+1}+\alpha _{i+1}$. Hence the sequences $(\alpha _i),$ and $(\beta _i)$ conform to the construction in the proof of Proposition 4.1, and so other parts of that proof yield (ii)–(vi). The next statement follows as in the proof of Lemma 3.5 using Lemma 2.7 and (iv).

Suppose that $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ is of Hahn type. We show that then $\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle$ is a Hahn space; the additional argument required for showing that $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\,\psi _{\beta })$ is of Hahn type is similar and left to the reader. So let $\delta _1,\, \delta _2\in \Gamma \langle \beta \rangle ^{\ne }$ satisfy $[\delta _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\delta _2]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$; we have to find $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}$ such that $[\delta _1-c\delta _2]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}< [\delta _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. Now

\[ \delta_1 = \gamma_1+\sum_i c_{i1}\beta_i, \quad \delta_2 = \gamma_2+\sum_i c_{i2}\beta_i,\quad \gamma_1,\gamma_2\in \Gamma, \]

with all $c_{i1},\, c_{i2}\in {\boldsymbol {k}}$, and $c_{i1}=c_{i2}=0$ for all but finitely many $i$. Consider first the case $[\delta _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\in [\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. Then $[\gamma _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}> [\beta _i]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ for all $i$ with $c_{i1}\ne 0$, by (i), (ii), (iii), and so $\delta _1=\gamma _1+ \alpha _1$ with $[\alpha _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}< [\gamma _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\delta _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$, and likewise $\delta _2=\gamma _2 + \alpha _2$ with $[\alpha _2]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}< [\gamma _2]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\delta _2]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. Take $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}$ such that $[\gamma _1-c\gamma _2]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}<[\gamma _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. Then $\delta _1-c\delta _2= \gamma _1-c\gamma _2+ \alpha _1-c\alpha _2$, so $[\delta _1-c\delta _2]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}<[\gamma _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\delta _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. Next, suppose $[\delta _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\notin [\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. Then $c_{i1}\ne 0$ for some $i$; let $j$ be the least such $i$. Then $[\gamma _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}<[\beta _j]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ and $[\delta _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\beta _j]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ by (ii). Now $j$ is also the least $i$ with $c_{i2}\ne 0$, in view of $[\delta _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\delta _2]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. Then $[\delta _1-c\delta _2]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}<[\delta _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ for $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}$ with $c_{j1}=cc_{j2}$.

Lemma 4.3 Let $\alpha _0,\,\ldots,\, \alpha _n,\, \beta _1,\,\ldots,\, \beta _n$ be as in (c)$_n$, and set $\Delta :=\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _n^{\dagger},$ so $\Delta ^{\dagger} =\Gamma ^{\dagger}$ and $\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle =\Delta \oplus {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _0\oplus \cdots \oplus {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _n$. Then:

  1. (i) $\Gamma ^{<}$ is cofinal in $\Delta ^{<};$

  2. (ii) $\beta _0^{\dagger},\, \ldots,\, \beta _{n}^{\dagger} \notin \Gamma,$, and thus $[\beta _0]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}},\,\ldots,\,[\beta _n]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\notin [\Delta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}};$

  3. (iii) $\beta _0^{\dagger} < \cdots < \beta _n^{\dagger},$ and thus $[\beta _0]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}> \cdots > [\beta _n]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}};$

  4. (iv) $\Psi _{\beta } = \Psi \cup \{\beta _0^{\dagger},\,\ldots,\, \beta _n^{\dagger} \}$ and $[\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\Delta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\cup \big \{[\beta _0]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}},\,\ldots,\,[\beta _n]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\big \};$

  5. (v) there is no $\gamma \in \Delta + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _0+\cdots + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _{n-1}$ with $0 < \gamma < \Gamma ^{>};$

  6. (vi) if $|\beta _n|\geqslant \alpha$ for some $\alpha \in \Gamma ^{>},$ then $\Gamma ^{<}$ is cofinal in $\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle ^{<}$ and so a gap in $(\Delta,\, \psi _{\Delta }),$ if any, remains a gap in $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\, \psi _{\beta });$

  7. (vii) if $|\beta _n|< \Gamma ^{>},$ then $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\, \psi _{\beta })$ is grounded with $\max \Psi _{\beta }=\beta _n^{\dagger} ;$

  8. (viii) if $(\Delta,\, \psi _{\Delta })$ has no gap, then there is no $\eta \in \Gamma \langle \beta \rangle$ with $\Psi < \eta < (\Gamma ^{>})'$, and so $\Gamma ^{<}$ is cofinal in $\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle ^{<}$ and $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\, \psi _{\beta })$ has asymptotic integration.

Proof. As to (i), if $\delta \in \Delta$ and $\Gamma ^{<}< \delta < 0$, then $\Psi < \delta ^{\dagger}$, contradicting $\Delta ^{\dagger} =\Gamma ^{\dagger}$. Item (ii) follows from the ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-linear independence of $\beta _0,\,\ldots,\, \beta _n,\, \beta _n^{\dagger}$ over $\Gamma$ and from $\beta _{i}^{\dagger} =\beta _{i+1}+\alpha _{i+1}$ for $i < n$. Next, we obtain (iii) from Claim 1 in the proof of Proposition 4.1, and then (iv) follows easily. As to (v), by (ii) and (iii) we have

\[ [\Delta+ {\boldsymbol{k}}\beta_0+\cdots + {\boldsymbol{k}}\beta_{n-1}]_{{\boldsymbol{k}}} = [\Delta]_{{\boldsymbol{k}}}\cup\big\{[\beta_0]_{{\boldsymbol{k}}},\ldots, [\beta_{n-1}]_{{\boldsymbol{k}}}\big\}. \]

Thus, assuming towards a contradiction that (v) is false gives $\gamma \in \Delta \cup \{\beta _0,\,\ldots,\, \beta _{n-1}\}$ with $0 < |\gamma | < \Gamma ^{>}$. Then $\Psi <\gamma ^{\dagger} < (\Gamma ^{>})'$, and so $\gamma \notin \Delta$. Hence $\gamma =\beta _i$ with $i < n$, and so $\gamma ^{\dagger} \in \Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _0+ \cdots + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _n$, contradicting Claim 2 in the proof of Proposition 4.1 with $\gamma ^{\dagger}$ in the role of $\eta$. By similar arguments, if $0 < \gamma < \Gamma ^{>}$ for some $\gamma \in \Gamma \langle \beta \rangle$, then $0 < |\beta _n| < \Gamma ^{>}$. This gives (vi). For (vii), assume $|\beta _n|< \Gamma ^{>}$. Then (i), (iv), (v) give $[\beta _n]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=\min \![\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle ^{\ne }]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$, and thus $\max \Psi _\beta =\beta _n^{\dagger}$.

As to (viii), note first that $\Psi =\Psi _{\Delta }$. Assume $(\Delta,\, \psi _{\Delta })$ has no gap. Then $(\Delta,\, \psi _{\Delta })$ has asymptotic integration. Hence by Claim 2 in the proof of Proposition 4.1, applied to $\Delta$ instead of $\Gamma$, there is no $\eta \in \Gamma \langle \beta \rangle$ with $\Psi < \eta < (\Gamma ^{>})'$.

Lemma 4.4 Let $\alpha _0,\,\ldots,\, \alpha _n,\, \beta _0,\,\ldots,\, \beta _n$ be as in (d)$_n$. Then:

  1. (i) $\beta _0^{\dagger},\, \ldots,\, \beta _{n-1}^{\dagger} \notin \Gamma,$ $\beta _n^{\dagger} \notin \Psi,$ and thus $[\beta _0]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}},\,\ldots,\,[\beta _n]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\notin [\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}};$

  2. (ii) $\beta _0^{\dagger} < \cdots < \beta _n^{\dagger},$ and thus $[\beta _0]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}> \cdots > [\beta _n]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}};$

  3. (iii) $\Psi _{\beta } = \Psi \cup \{\beta _0^{\dagger},\,\ldots,\, \beta _n^{\dagger} \}$ and $[\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\cup \big \{[\beta _0]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}},\,\ldots,\,[\beta _n]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\big \};$

  4. (iv) there is no $\eta \in \Gamma \langle \beta \rangle$ with $\Psi < \eta < (\Gamma ^{>})';$

  5. (v) $\Gamma ^{<}$ is cofinal in $\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle ^{<},$ and $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\, \psi _{\beta })$ has asymptotic integration.

Proof. The first part of (i) follows from the recursion satisfied by $\beta _0,\,\ldots,\, \beta _n$, the ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-linear independence of $\beta _0,\,\ldots,\, \beta _n$ over $\Gamma$, and $\beta _n^{\dagger} \notin \Psi$. Claim 1 in the proof of Proposition 4.1 gives (ii), which together with (i) yields (iii). Claim 2 in that proof gives (iv), which has (v) as an easy consequence.

The next result is crucial in the proof of Theorem 0.1 in § 5. Here $(\Gamma ^*,\, \psi ^*)$ is equipped with an $H$-cut $P^*$, and we set $P:= P^*\cap \Gamma = \Psi ^{\downarrow }$, and $P_{\gamma }:=P^*\cap \Gamma \langle \gamma \rangle$ for $\gamma \in \Gamma ^*$, so we have the $H$-triples $(\Gamma,\, \psi,\, P),\, (\Gamma \langle \gamma \rangle,\, \psi _{\gamma },\, P_{\gamma }) \subseteq (\Gamma ^*,\, \psi ^*,\, P^*)$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$.

Lemma 4.5 Assume $(\Gamma ^*,\,\psi ^*)$ is closed, of Hahn type, and $\Gamma ^{<}$ is not cofinal in $(\Gamma ^*)^{<}$. Then for some $\delta \in (\Gamma ^*)^{>},$ all $\gamma \in \Gamma ^*$ with $|\beta -\gamma | < \delta$ yield an isomorphism $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\, \psi _{\beta },\, P_{\beta }) \to (\Gamma \langle \gamma \rangle,\, \psi _{\gamma },\, P_{\gamma })$ over $\Gamma$ sending $\beta$ to $\gamma$.

Proof. Suppose we are in Case (a) of Proposition 4.1. There are three subcases:

Subcase 1: $(\Gamma ^>)^{\dagger} < \eta < (\Gamma ^>)'$ and $\eta \in P^*$ for some $\eta \in \Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta$. Fix such $\eta$ and recall from Case 1 in the proof of Lemma 3.4 that $\Gamma$ is dense in $\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\eta =\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta$. Thus, if $\varepsilon \in \Gamma ^*$ and $0 < \varepsilon < \Gamma ^{>}$, then $(\Gamma ^>)^{\dagger} < \eta -\varepsilon < \eta$. Moreover, $P^*$ has no largest element, so we can take $\varepsilon \in (\Gamma ^*)^{>}$ so small that for all $\zeta \in \Gamma ^*$ with $|\eta -\zeta |<\varepsilon$ we have $(\Gamma ^>)^{\dagger} < \zeta < (\Gamma ^>)'$ and $\zeta \in P^*$; in particular, such $\zeta$ realizes the same cut in $\Gamma$ as $\eta$. Take $\alpha \in \Gamma$ and $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}^\times$ with $\beta =\alpha +c\eta$. Then for $\zeta$ as above and $\gamma := \alpha +c\zeta$ the condition $|\eta -\zeta |< \varepsilon$ amounts to $|\beta -\gamma |< \delta :=|c|\varepsilon$, with an isomorphism $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\, \psi _{\beta },\, P_{\beta }) \to (\Gamma \langle \gamma \rangle,\, \psi _{\gamma },\, P_{\gamma })$ over $\Gamma$ sending $\beta$ to $\gamma$.

Subcase 2: $(\Gamma ^>)^{\dagger} < \eta < (\Gamma ^>)'$ and $\eta \notin P^*$ for some $\eta \in \Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta$. This can be treated in the same way as Subcase 1.

Subcase 3: there is no $\eta \in \Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta$ with $(\Gamma ^>)^{\dagger} < \eta < (\Gamma ^>)'$. Take $\delta \in \Gamma ^*$ such that $0 < \delta < \Gamma ^{>}$. Then all $\gamma \in \Gamma ^*$ with $|\gamma -\beta |< \delta$ realize the same cut in $\Gamma$ as $\beta$: otherwise we would have $\alpha \in \Gamma$ with $0<|\alpha -\beta |< \Gamma ^{>}$, so $(\Gamma ^>)^{\dagger} < (\alpha -\beta )^{\dagger} < (\Gamma ^>)'$, a contradiction. Now $(\Gamma ^*,\, \psi ^*)$ is of Hahn type, so $[\Gamma +{\boldsymbol {k}}\beta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. As in Case 3 in the proof of Lemma 3.4 this yields for any such $\gamma$ an isomorphism $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\, \psi _{\beta },\, P_{\beta }) \to (\Gamma \langle \gamma \rangle,\, \psi _{\gamma },\, P_{\gamma })$ over $\Gamma$ sending $\beta$ to $\gamma$.

Assume we are in Case (b) of Proposition 4.1, and let $(\alpha _i)$ and $(\beta _i)$ be as in that case. Let $\varepsilon \in \Gamma ^*$ be such that $[\varepsilon ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}< [\beta _0]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. Then $\beta _0+\varepsilon = (\beta +\varepsilon )-\alpha _0$, $[\beta _0+\varepsilon ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\beta _0]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$, and thus $(\beta _0+\varepsilon )^{\dagger} =\beta _0^{\dagger}$. It follows that with $\beta +\varepsilon$ instead of $\beta$ we are also in case (b), with associated sequences $(\alpha _i)$ and $(\beta _{i,\varepsilon })$, with $\beta _{0,\varepsilon }:=\beta _0+\varepsilon$ and $\beta _{i,\varepsilon }:= \beta _i$ for $i\geqslant 1$. As noted in the proof of Lemma 4.2, the sequences $(\alpha _i)$, $(\beta _i)$ conform to the construction in the proof of Proposition 4.1, and so the latter proof yields an isomorphism $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\, \psi _{\beta },\, P_{\beta }) \to (\Gamma \langle \beta +\varepsilon \rangle,\, \psi _{\beta +\varepsilon },\, P_{\beta +\varepsilon })$ over $\Gamma$ that sends $\beta _i$ to $\beta _{i,\varepsilon }$ for each $i$, and thus $\beta$ to $\beta +\varepsilon$.

Next, assume we are in Case (c)$_n$ of Proposition 4.1, and let $\alpha _0,\,\ldots,\, \alpha _n,\,\beta _0,\,\ldots,\, \beta _n$ be as in that case. As before, let $\varepsilon \in \Gamma ^*$ be such that $[\varepsilon ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}< [\beta _0]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. Then $\beta _0+\varepsilon = (\beta +\varepsilon )-\alpha _0$, $[\beta _0+\varepsilon ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\beta _0]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$, so $(\beta _0+\varepsilon )^{\dagger} =\beta _0^{\dagger}$. Hence with $\beta +\varepsilon$ instead of $\beta$ we are again in case (c)$_n$, with associated sequences $\alpha _0,\,\ldots,\, \alpha _n$ and $\beta _{0,\varepsilon },\, \ldots,\, \beta _{n,\varepsilon }$, with $\beta _{0,\varepsilon }:=\beta _0+\varepsilon$ and $\beta _{i,\varepsilon }:= \beta _i$ for $1\leqslant i\leqslant n$. Note also that $\beta$ and $\beta +\varepsilon$ give rise to the same $\Delta =\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}}\beta _n^{\dagger} =\Gamma + {\boldsymbol {k}} \beta _{n,\varepsilon }^{\dagger}$. It now follows from Lemma 4.3 that we have an isomorphism $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\, \psi _{\beta }) \to (\Gamma \langle \beta +\varepsilon \rangle,\, \psi _{\beta +\varepsilon })$ of $H$-couples over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ that is the identity on $\Delta$ and sends $\beta _i$ to $\beta _{i,\varepsilon }$ for each $i\leqslant n$, and thus, $\beta$ to $\beta +\varepsilon$. Since $\beta$ and $\beta +\varepsilon$ yield the same $\Delta$, it follows easily from (vi), (vii), (viii) of Lemma 4.3 that this isomorphism maps $P_{\beta }$ onto $P_{\beta +\varepsilon }$.

Finally, assume we are in Case (d)$_n$ of Proposition 4.1, and let $\alpha _0,\,\ldots,\, \alpha _n,\,\beta _0,\,\ldots,\, \beta _n$ be as in that case. Let $\varepsilon \in \Gamma ^*$ be such that $[\varepsilon ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}< [\beta _0]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. Then $\beta _0+\varepsilon = {(\beta +\varepsilon )-\alpha _0}$, $[\beta _0+\varepsilon ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\beta _0]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$, so $(\beta _0+\varepsilon )^{\dagger} =\beta _0^{\dagger}$. Hence with $\beta +\varepsilon$ instead of $\beta$ we are again in case (d)$_n$, with associated sequences $\alpha _0,\,\ldots,\, \alpha _n$ and $\beta _{0,\varepsilon },\, \ldots,\, \beta _{n,\varepsilon }$, with $\beta _{0,\varepsilon }:=\beta _0+\varepsilon$ and $\beta _{i,\varepsilon }:= \beta _i$ for $1\leqslant i\leqslant n$. Then Lemma 4.4 yields an isomorphism $(\Gamma \langle \beta \rangle,\, \psi _{\beta },\, P_\beta ) \to (\Gamma \langle \beta +\varepsilon \rangle, \psi _{\beta +\varepsilon },\, P_{\beta +\varepsilon })$ of $H$-triples over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ that is the identity on $\Gamma$ and sends $\beta _i$ to $\beta _{i,\varepsilon }$ for each $i\leqslant n$, and thus $\beta$ to $\beta +\varepsilon$.

5. Closed $H$-couples of Hahn type

So far we have treated $H$-couples over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ as one-sorted structures, by keeping ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ fixed and having for each scalar $c$ a separate unary function symbol that is interpreted as scalar multiplication by $c$. We now go to the setting where an $H$-couple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ is viewed as a $2$-sorted structure with ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ as a second sort, and thus with “Hahn type” as a first-order condition. Extending an $H$-couple may now involve extending ${\boldsymbol {k}}$, so we begin with a subsection on the process of scalar extension for Hahn spaces. We remind the reader that the ordered scalar field ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ is not necessarily real closed.

Scalar extension

Let $\Gamma$ be a Hahn space over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$, and let ${\boldsymbol {k}}^*$ be an ordered field extension of ${\boldsymbol {k}}$. Then we have the vector space $\Gamma _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}:= {\boldsymbol {k}}^*\otimes _{{\boldsymbol {k}}} \Gamma$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}^*$. We have the ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-linear embedding $\gamma \mapsto 1\otimes \gamma \colon \Gamma \to \Gamma _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}$ via which we identify $\Gamma$ with a ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-linear subspace of $\Gamma _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}$. We make $\Gamma _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}$ into a Hahn space over ${\boldsymbol {k}}^*$ as follows: for any $\gamma \in \Gamma _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}^{\ne }$ we have $\gamma =c_1\gamma _1+\cdots + c_m\gamma _m$ with $m\geqslant 1$, $c_1,\,\ldots,\, c_m\in ({\boldsymbol {k}}^*)^\times$, $\gamma _1\ldots,\, \gamma _m\in \Gamma ^{>}$, $[\gamma _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}} > \cdots >[\gamma _m]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$; then $\gamma >0$ iff $c_1>0$. This makes $\Gamma$ into an ordered ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-linear subspace of $\Gamma _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}$, and we have an order-preserving bijection ${[\gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\to [\gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}\colon [\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}} \to [\Gamma _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}}$.

Lemma 5.1 Assume $[\Gamma ^{\ne }]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ has no least element. Then for every $\gamma ^{*}\in \Gamma _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^{*}}\setminus \Gamma$ there is an element $\varepsilon \in \Gamma ^{>}$ such that $|\gamma ^{*}-\gamma |>\varepsilon$ for all $\gamma \in \Gamma$.

Proof. Let $\gamma ^*\in \Gamma _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}\setminus \Gamma$, so $\gamma ^*=c_1\gamma _1+\cdots + c_m\gamma _m$ with $m\geqslant 1$, $c_1,\,\ldots,\, c_m\in ({\boldsymbol {k}}^*)^\times$, $\gamma _1\ldots,\, \gamma _m\in \Gamma ^{>}$, $[\gamma _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}} > \cdots >[\gamma _m]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. To show that $\gamma ^*$ has the claimed property we can assume $c_1\notin {\boldsymbol {k}}$. Take any $\varepsilon \in \Gamma ^{>}$ with $[\varepsilon ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}} < [\gamma _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$, and assume towards a contradiction that $\gamma \in \Gamma$ and $|\gamma ^*-\gamma |\leqslant \varepsilon$. Then $[\gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}=[\gamma ^*]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}=[\gamma _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}$, so $[\gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\gamma _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$, and hence $[\gamma -c\gamma _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}<[\gamma _1]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ with $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}$. In view of

\[ \gamma^*-\gamma = (c_1-c)\gamma_1 + c_2\gamma_2 + \cdots + c_m\gamma_m - (\gamma-c\gamma_1) \]

and $c_1\ne c$, this yields a contradiction.

We also have the following universal property:

Corollary 5.2 Any embedding $\Gamma \to \Gamma ^*$ of ordered vector spaces over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ into an ordered vector space $\Gamma ^*$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}^*$ such that the induced map $[\Gamma ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}} \to [\Gamma ^*]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}$ is injective extends uniquely to an embedding $\Gamma _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*} \to \Gamma ^*$ of ordered vector spaces over ${\boldsymbol {k}}^*$.

Let $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ be an $H$-couple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ of Hahn type and ${\boldsymbol {k}}^*$ an ordered field extension of ${\boldsymbol {k}}$. The $H$-couple $(\Gamma,\, \psi )_{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}:= (\Gamma _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*},\, \psi _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*})$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}^*$ is determined by requiring that $\psi _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}$ extends $\psi$. Note that then $(\Gamma,\, \psi )_{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}$ is also of Hahn type and has the same $\Psi$-set as $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$. The following is close to [Reference Aschenbrenner and van den Dries1, Lemma 3.7], whose proof uses a form of Hahn's Embedding Theorem. Here we use instead Lemma 5.1.

Lemma 5.3 If $\gamma \in \Gamma$ is a gap in $(\Gamma,\,\psi ),$ then $\gamma$ remains a gap in $(\Gamma,\,\psi )_{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}$. If $\gamma ^*$ is a gap in $(\Gamma,\,\psi )_{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}$, then $\gamma ^*\in \Gamma$. Thus, $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$ has asymptotic integration if and only if $(\Gamma,\, \psi )_{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}$ has asymptotic integration.

Proof. Suppose towards a contradiction that $\gamma \in \Gamma$ is a gap in $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$, but not in $(\Gamma,\,\psi )_{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}$. Then $\gamma =\alpha '$ with $\alpha \in \Gamma _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}^{>}\setminus \Gamma$. From $\gamma < (\Gamma ^{>})'$ we get $0<\alpha <\Gamma ^{>}$, but this contradicts that by Lemma 5.1 we have $|\alpha |> \varepsilon$ for some $\varepsilon \in \Gamma ^{>}$.

Next, assume $\gamma ^*$ is a gap in $(\Gamma,\,\psi )_{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}$. Then $\Psi < \gamma ^* < (\Gamma ^{>})'$, and for all $\varepsilon \in \Gamma ^{>}$ there are $\alpha \in \Psi$ and $\beta \in (\Gamma ^{>})'$ (namely $\alpha := \varepsilon ^{\dagger}$ and $\beta := \varepsilon '$) with $\beta -\alpha \leqslant \varepsilon$. In view of Lemma 5.1 this yields $\gamma ^*\in \Gamma$.

Normalized $H$-couples

Let $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$ be an $H$-couple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$. By [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2, § 9.2], if $\Psi \cap \Gamma ^{>}\ne \emptyset$, then $\psi (\gamma )=\gamma$ for a unique $\gamma \in \Gamma ^{>}$; this unique fixed point of $\psi$ on $\Gamma ^{>}$ is then denoted by $1$. Referring to $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ as a normalized $H$-couple means that ${\Psi \cap \Gamma ^{>}\ne \emptyset }$, and that we consider $\Gamma$ as equipped with this fixed point $1$ as a distinguished element. (The term “normalized” is justified, because for any $H$-couple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ with underlying ordered vector space $\Gamma \ne \{0\}$ we can arrange ${\Psi \cap \Gamma ^{>}\ne \emptyset }$ by replacing its function $\psi$ with a suitable “shift” $\alpha +\psi$ where $\alpha \in \Gamma$.) For minor technical reasons, it is convenient to restrict our attention in the remainder of this paper to normalized $H$-couples; this is hardly a loss of generality, as we saw. Note also that the $H$-couple of $\mathbb {T}$ is normalized by taking $1=v(x^{-1})$.

Below we construe a normalized $H$-couple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ as a $2$-sorted structure

\[ \boldsymbol{\Gamma} = \big((\Gamma,\psi), {\boldsymbol{k}}; \operatorname{sc}\!\big) \]

where $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ is an $H$-couple as defined in the beginning of § 1, ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ is an ordered field, and $\operatorname {sc}\colon {\boldsymbol {k}}\times \Gamma \to \Gamma$ is a scalar multiplication that makes $\Gamma$ into an ordered vector space over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ (but we shall write $c\gamma$ instead of $\operatorname {sc}(c,\,\gamma )$ for $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}$ and $\gamma \in \Gamma$), such that $\psi (c\gamma )=\psi (\gamma )$ for $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}^\times$, $\gamma \in \Gamma$; in addition we assume $\Gamma$ to be equipped with an element $1>0$ such that $\psi (1)=1$. Such $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }$ is said to be of Hahn type if the $H$-couple $(\Gamma,\,\psi )$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ is of Hahn type as defined in § 1. In the same way, we may consider a normalized $H$-triple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ as a $2$-sorted structure

\[ \boldsymbol{\Gamma}=\big((\Gamma,\psi,P), {\boldsymbol{k}}; \operatorname{sc}\!\big). \]

The language and theory of normalized $H$-triples of Hahn type

We construe a normalized $H$-triple $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }=((\Gamma,\,\psi,\,P),\, {\boldsymbol {k}}; \operatorname {sc}\!)$ of Hahn type as an $\mathcal {L}_H$-structure, where $\mathcal {L}_H$ is the two-sorted language with the following non-logical symbols:

  1. (i) $P,\,<,\,0,\,1$,$\infty,\,-,\, +,\,\psi$, interpreted as usual in $\Gamma _{\infty }:=\Gamma \cup \{\infty \}$, the linear ordering on $\Gamma$ being extended to a linear order on $\Gamma _{\infty }$ by $\gamma <\infty$ for $\gamma \in \Gamma$, and with $\infty$ serving as a default value by setting $-\infty =\infty$, $\gamma +\infty =\infty +\gamma =\infty +\infty =\psi (0)=\psi (\infty )=\infty$ for $\gamma \in \Gamma$;

  2. (ii) $<,\, 0,\, 1$, $\infty,\, -,\,+,\,\cdot$, interpreted as usual in ${\boldsymbol {k}}_{\infty }:={\boldsymbol {k}}\cup \{\infty \}$, the linear ordering on ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ being extended to a linear order on ${\boldsymbol {k}}_{\infty }$ by $c<\infty$ for $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}$, and with $\infty$ serving as a default value by setting $-\infty =\infty$, $c+\infty =\infty +c=\infty +\infty =c\infty =\infty c= \infty \infty =\infty$ for $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}$;

  3. (iii) a symbol $\operatorname {sc}$ for the map ${\boldsymbol {k}}_{\infty }\times \Gamma _{\infty } \to \Gamma _{\infty }$ that is the scalar multiplication on ${\boldsymbol {k}}\times \Gamma$, and taking the value $\infty$ at all other points of ${\boldsymbol {k}}_{\infty }\times \Gamma _{\infty }$;

  4. (iv) a symbol $:$ for the function $\Gamma _{\infty }^2\to {\boldsymbol {k}}_{\infty }$ that assigns to every $(\alpha,\,\beta )\in \Gamma ^2$ with $[\alpha ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}\leqslant [\beta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$ and $\beta \ne 0$ the unique scalar $\alpha :\beta =c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}$ such that $[{\alpha -c\beta }]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}<[\beta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$, and assigns to all other pairs in $\Gamma _{\infty }^2$ the value $\infty$.

The symbols in (i) should be distinguished from those in (ii) even though we use the same written signs for convenience. The two default values $\infty$ are included to make all primitives totally defined. Note that in (iv) we have $\alpha :\beta =0$ if $[\alpha ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}} < [\beta ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$.

Using $a1:b1=a/b$ for $a,\,b\in {\boldsymbol {k}}$ with $b\ne 0$, we see that a substructure of a normalized $H$-triple of Hahn type is also a normalized $H$-triple of Hahn type, with possibly smaller scalar field. Thus, the $\mathcal {L}_H$-theory of normalized $H$-triples of Hahn type has a universal axiomatization (which would be easy to specify). Let there be given normalized $H$-triples of Hahn type,

\[ \boldsymbol{\Gamma}_0 = \big((\Gamma_0,\psi_0,P_0), {\boldsymbol{k}}_0; \operatorname{sc}_0\!\big)\ \text{ and }\ \boldsymbol{\Gamma} = \big((\Gamma,\psi,P), {\boldsymbol{k}}; \operatorname{sc}\!\big). \]

An embedding $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }_0 \to \boldsymbol {\Gamma }$ is a pair $i=(i_{\operatorname {v}},\, i_{\operatorname {s}})$ whose vector part $i_{\operatorname {v}}\colon \Gamma _0\to \Gamma$ is an embedding of ordered abelian group and whose scalar part $i_{\operatorname {s}}\colon {\boldsymbol {k}}_0 \to {\boldsymbol {k}}$ is an embedding of ordered fields such that $i_{\operatorname {v}}(c\gamma )=i_{\operatorname {s}}(c)i_{\operatorname {v}}(\gamma )$ and $\gamma \in P_0\Leftrightarrow i_{\operatorname {v}}(\gamma )\in P$ for all $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}_0$ and $\gamma \in \Gamma _0$, and $i_{\operatorname {v}}(\psi _0(\gamma ))=\psi (i_{\operatorname {v}}(\gamma ))$ for all non-zero $\gamma \in \Gamma _0$ (and so $i_{\operatorname {v}}(1)=1$ and $i_c(\alpha :\beta )=i_{\operatorname {v}}(\alpha ):i_{\operatorname {v}}(\beta )$ for all $\alpha,\,\beta \in \Gamma$). If ${\boldsymbol {k}}_0={\boldsymbol {k}}$, then an embedding $e\colon (\Gamma _0,\, \psi _0,\, P_0) \to (\Gamma,\,\psi,\,P)$ of $H$-triples over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ in the usual sense yields an embedding $(e,\,\text {id}_{{\boldsymbol {k}}})\colon \boldsymbol {\Gamma }_0 \to \boldsymbol {\Gamma }$ as above.

Quantifier elimination

Let $T_H$ be the $\mathcal {L}_H$-theory of normalized closed $H$-triples of Hahn type, and recall that the $H$-couple of $\mathbb {T}$ is naturally a model of $T_H$. In this subsection, we let $\boldsymbol {\Gamma } = ((\Gamma,\,\psi,\,P),\, {\boldsymbol {k}}; \operatorname {sc}\!)$ and $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^* = ((\Gamma ^*,\,\psi ^*,\,P^*),\, {\boldsymbol {k}}^*; \operatorname {sc}^*\!)$ denote normalized closed $H$-triples of Hahn type, construed as models of $T_H$. The key embedding result is as follows:

Proposition 5.4 Assume $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$ is $\kappa$-saturated for $\kappa =|\Gamma |^+$. Let $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }_0$ be a substructure of $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }$ with scalar field ${\boldsymbol {k}}_0$. Let an embedding $i_0\colon \boldsymbol {\Gamma }_0\to \boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$ be given, and an embedding $e\colon {\boldsymbol {k}} \to {\boldsymbol {k}}^*$ of ordered fields such that $e|_{{\boldsymbol {k}}_0}=(i_0)_{\operatorname {s}}$. Then $i_0$ can be extended to an embedding $i\colon \boldsymbol {\Gamma }\to \boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$ such that $i_{\operatorname {s}}=e$.

Proof. By Corollary 5.2 on extending scalars, the remarks following it, and (to handle the $P$-predicate) Lemma 5.3 we can reduce to the case ${\boldsymbol {k}}_0={\boldsymbol {k}}$. It remains to appeal to the embedding result established in the proof of Theorem 3.3.

In what follows, formula means $\mathcal {L}_H$-formula. Let $x=(x_1,\,\ldots,\, x_m)$ denote a tuple of distinct scalar variables and $y=(y_1,\,\ldots,\,y_n)$ a tuple of distinct vector variables.

Corollary 5.5 Suppose that $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }$ is a substructure of $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$. Then

\[ \boldsymbol{\Gamma}\preccurlyeq \boldsymbol{\Gamma}^* \text{ (as} \mathcal{L}_H \text{-structures)}\quad \Longleftrightarrow\quad {\boldsymbol{k}} \preccurlyeq {\boldsymbol{k}}^* \text{(as ordered fields).} \]

Proof. The direction $\Rightarrow$ being trivial, we assume ${\boldsymbol {k}}\preccurlyeq {\boldsymbol {k}}^*$ and shall derive $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }\preccurlyeq \boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$. By induction on formulas $\phi (x,\,y)$ (with $x$ and $y$ as above) we show that for all $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }$ and $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$ as in the hypothesis of the lemma and all $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}^m$ and $\gamma \in \Gamma ^n$,

(\unicode{x002A})\begin{equation} \boldsymbol{\Gamma}\models \phi(c,\gamma)\quad \Longleftrightarrow\quad \boldsymbol{\Gamma}^*\models \phi(c,\gamma). \end{equation}

For the inductive step, let $\phi =\exists z \theta$, where $\theta =\theta (x,\,y,\,z)$ is a formula and $z$ is a single variable of the scalar or vector sort. The direction $\Rightarrow$ in (??) holds by the (implicit) inductive assumption. Assume $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*\models \phi (c,\,\gamma )$ where $c\in {\boldsymbol {k}}^m$ and $\gamma \in \Gamma ^n$. Take a $\kappa$-saturated elementary extension $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }_1$ of $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }$, where $\kappa =|\Gamma ^*|^+$. Let ${\boldsymbol {k}}_1$ be the scalar field of $\Gamma _1$. Then we have an elementary embedding $e\colon {\boldsymbol {k}}^*\to {\boldsymbol {k}}_1$ that is the identity on ${\boldsymbol {k}}$. Proposition 5.4 (with $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }$, $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$, $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }_1$ in the roles of $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }_0$, $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }$, $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$) gives an embedding $i\colon \boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*\to \boldsymbol {\Gamma }_1$ where $i_{\operatorname {s}}=e$ and $i_{\operatorname {v}}$ is the identity on $\Gamma$. By the (tacit) inductive hypothesis on $\theta$ we obtain $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }_1\models \phi (c,\,\gamma )$, and thus $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }\models \phi (c,\,\gamma )$.

With $x$, $y$ as above, call a formula $\eta (x,\,y)$ a scalar formula if it has the form $\zeta (s_1(x,\,y),\,\ldots,\, s_N(x,\,y))$ where $\zeta (z_1,\,\ldots,\, z_N)$ is a formula in the language of ordered rings (as specified in (ii) of the description of $\mathcal {L}_H$), where $z_1,\,\ldots,\, z_N$ are distinct scalar variables and $s_1(x,\,y),\,\ldots,\, s_N(x,\,y)$ are scalar-valued terms of $\mathcal {L}_H$.

Theorem 5.6 Every formula $\phi (x,\,y)$ is $T_H$-equivalent to a boolean combination of scalar formulas $\eta (x,\,y)$ and atomic formulas $\alpha (x,\,y)$.

As a consequence, extending $T_H$ by axioms that the scalar field is real closed gives outright QE, without requiring scalar formulas.

Proof. Suppose $(c,\,\gamma )\in {\boldsymbol {k}}^m\times \Gamma ^n$ and $(c^*,\, \gamma ^*)\in ({\boldsymbol {k}}^*)^m\times (\Gamma ^*)^n$ satisfy the same scalar formulas $\eta (x,\,y)$ and atomic formulas $\alpha (x,\,y)$ in $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }$ and $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$, respectively. It suffices to derive from this assumption that $(c,\,\gamma )$ and $(c^*,\,\gamma ^*)$ satisfy the same formulas in $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }$ and $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$. We may assume that $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$ is $\kappa$-saturated where $\kappa =|\Gamma |^+$. Let $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }_0$ with scalar field ${\boldsymbol {k}}_0$ be the substructure of $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }$ generated by $(c,\,\gamma )$. Since $(c,\,\gamma )$ and $(c^*,\,\gamma ^*)$ realize the same atomic formulas $\alpha (x,\,y)$, we have an embedding $i_0\colon \boldsymbol {\Gamma }_0\to \boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$ such that $i_0(c)=c^*$ and $i_0(\gamma )=\gamma ^*$. They also realize the same scalar formulas $\eta (x,\,y)$, so we have an elementary embedding $e\colon {\boldsymbol {k}}\to {\boldsymbol {k}}^*$ agreeing with $(i_0)_{\operatorname {s}}$ on ${\boldsymbol {k}}_0$. Proposition 5.4 then yields an embedding $i\colon \boldsymbol {\Gamma }\to \boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$ extending $i_0$ with $i_{\operatorname {s}}=e$. Then $i$ is an elementary embedding by Corollary 5.5, so $(c,\,\gamma )$ and $(c^*,\,\gamma ^*)$ do indeed satisfy the same formulas in $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }$ and $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$.

Discrete definable sets

We are finally ready to prove the theorem announced in the introduction. We state it here in its natural general setting:

Theorem 5.7 Let $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }=((\Gamma,\,\psi,\,P),\, {\boldsymbol {k}}; \operatorname {sc}\!)$ be a normalized closed $H$-triple of Hahn type and let $X\subseteq \Gamma$ be definable in $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }$. Then the following are equivalent:

  1. (i) $X$ is contained in a finite-dimensional ${\boldsymbol {k}}$-linear subspace of $\Gamma ;$

  2. (ii) $X$ is discrete;

  3. (iii) $X$ has empty interior in $\Gamma$.

Proof. The direction (i) $\Rightarrow$ (ii) holds by Lemma 1.2. The direction (ii) $\Rightarrow$ (iii) is obvious. (These two implications do not need $X$ to be definable.)

As to (iii) $\Rightarrow$ (i), assume $X$ has empty interior. Take a formula $\phi (y)$ over $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }$ in a single vector variable $y$ that defines the set $X$ in $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }$. We use Theorem 5.6 to arrange that $\phi (y)$ is a boolean combination of scalar formulas over $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }$ and atomic formulas over $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }$. Take a $|\Gamma |^+$-saturated elementary extension $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*=((\Gamma ^*,\, \psi ^*,\,P^*),\,{\boldsymbol {k}}^*;\operatorname {sc}^*\!)$ of $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }$, and let $X^*\subseteq \Gamma ^*$ be defined by $\phi (y)$ in $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$. We identify $\Gamma _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}$ with ${\boldsymbol {k}}^*\Gamma \subseteq \Gamma ^*$ in the usual way. We Claim that $X^*\subseteq \Gamma _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}$. (This gives (i) by Lemma 1.3.) Consider the substructure $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }_{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}=((\Gamma _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*},\,\psi _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*},\, P_{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}),\,{\boldsymbol {k}}^*;\operatorname {sc}^*\!)$ of $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$; it has asymptotic integration by Lemma 5.3. Let $X_{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}\subseteq \Gamma _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}$ be defined in $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }_{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}$ by $\phi (y)$. Then $X_{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}=X^*\cap \Gamma _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}$, so our claim amounts to $X^*=X_{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}$. Suppose towards a contradiction that $\gamma ^*\in X^*\setminus X_{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}$. In particular, $\gamma ^*\in \Gamma ^*\setminus \Gamma _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}$. Saturation yields an $\varepsilon \in \Gamma ^*$ such that $0 < \varepsilon < c^*\gamma$ for all positive $c^*$ in ${\boldsymbol {k}}^*$ and all positive $\gamma \in \Gamma$, so $0 < \varepsilon < \Gamma _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}^{>}$, and thus $\Gamma _{{\boldsymbol {k}}^*}^{>}$ is not coinitial in $(\Gamma ^*)^{>}$. Lemma 4.5 then yields a $\delta >0$ in $\Gamma ^*$ such that all $\gamma \in \Gamma ^*$ with $|\gamma -\gamma ^*|< \delta$ yield an isomorphism

\[ \big(\Gamma_{{\boldsymbol{k}}^*}\langle\gamma^*\rangle, \psi_{\gamma^*}, P_{\gamma^*}\big)\ \cong\ \big(\Gamma_{{\boldsymbol{k}}^*}\langle\gamma\rangle, \psi_{\gamma}, P_{\gamma}\big)\ \subseteq\ \big(\Gamma^*, \psi^*, P^*\big) \]

of $H$-triples over ${\boldsymbol {k}}^*$ sending $\gamma ^*$ to $\gamma$. Hence $s(\gamma ^*)=s(\gamma )$ for such $\gamma$ and any scalar-valued $\mathcal {L}_H$-term $s(y)$ over $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }$, and so $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*\models \phi (\gamma )$ for those $\gamma$. Thus, the interval $(\gamma ^*-\delta,\, \gamma ^*+\delta )$ in $\Gamma ^*$ lies entirely in $X^*$, contradicting that $X^*$ is discrete in $\Gamma ^*$.

6. Further results about closed $H$-couples

We briefly return to the one-sorted setting of $H$-couples (or $H$-triples) and give two easy applications of Theorem 3.3.

Definable closure

Let $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*=(\Gamma ^*,\, \psi ^*,\,P^*)$ be a closed $H$-triple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$. Then we have the notion of the definable closure of a set $\Gamma \subseteq \Gamma ^*$ in $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$, and thus of such a set $\Gamma$ being definably closed in $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$. If $\Gamma \subseteq \Gamma ^*$ is definably closed in $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$, then $\Gamma$ is (the underlying set of) a subgroup of $\Gamma ^*$ with $\psi ^*(\Gamma ^{\ne })\subseteq \Gamma$, and thus we have an $H$-triple $(\Gamma,\, \psi,\, P)$ over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ with $(\Gamma,\, \psi,\, P)\subseteq \boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$.

Proposition 6.1 Let $(\Gamma,\, \psi,\, P)$ be an $H$-triple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ with $(\Gamma,\, \psi,\, P)\subseteq \boldsymbol {\Gamma }$. Then:

\[ \Gamma\text{ is definably closed in }(\Gamma^*, \psi^*,P^*)\quad \Longleftrightarrow\quad (\Gamma, \psi)\text{ has asymptotic integration.} \]

Proof. For $\Rightarrow$, note that for every $\gamma \in \Gamma$ there is a unique $\alpha \in (\Gamma ^*)^{\ne }$ with $\gamma =\alpha '$.

For the converse, assume that $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$ has asymptotic integration (so $P=\Psi ^{\downarrow }$). Iterating the construction of Lemma 3.1, we obtain an increasing continuous chain

\[ \big((\Gamma_\lambda,\psi_\lambda, P_\lambda)\big)_{\lambda<\nu} \qquad(\text{with $\nu$ an ordinal)} \]

of $H$-triples contained in $(\Gamma ^*,\, \psi ^*,\, P^*)$ as substructures, with $(\Gamma _0,\, \psi _0,\, P_0)=(\Gamma,\, \psi,\, P)$, such that every $(\Gamma _\lambda,\,\psi _\lambda,\, P_\lambda )$ has asymptotic integration with $P_{\lambda }$ being the downward closure of $\Psi _0$ in $\Gamma _{\lambda }$, and such that the union

\[ (\Gamma^{\operatorname{c}}, \psi^{\operatorname{c}}, P^{\operatorname{c}})\ :=\ \bigcup_{\lambda< \nu}(\Gamma_\lambda,\psi_\lambda, P_\lambda) \]

is closed. The reference to Lemma 3.1 means that for $\lambda < \lambda +1<\nu$ we have $\Gamma _{\lambda +1}=\Gamma _{\lambda }\oplus {\boldsymbol {k}}\alpha _{\lambda }$ with $\alpha _{\lambda }>0$ and $\alpha _{\lambda }^{\dagger} \in P_{\lambda }\setminus \psi _{\lambda }(\Gamma _{\lambda }^{\ne })$. That the chain is continuous means that $(\Gamma _\mu,\,\psi _\lambda,\, P_\mu )=\bigcup _{\lambda <\mu }(\Gamma _\lambda,\,\psi _\lambda,\, P_\lambda )$ for limit ordinals $\mu < \nu$. Any such $(\Gamma ^{\operatorname {c}},\, \psi ^{\operatorname {c}},\, P^{\operatorname {c}})$ is clearly, an $H$-closure of $(\Gamma,\, \psi,\, P)$, which explains the superscript $\operatorname {c}$. Since $(\Gamma ^{\operatorname {c}},\, \psi ^{\operatorname {c}},\, P^{\operatorname {c}})\preccurlyeq (\Gamma ^*,\,\psi ^*,\,P^*)$, any element of $\Gamma ^*$ that is definable in $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$ over $\Gamma$ must lie in $\Gamma ^{\operatorname {c}}$. So let $\gamma ^{\operatorname {c}}\in \Gamma ^{\operatorname {c}}\setminus \Gamma$; to show that then $\gamma ^{\operatorname {c}}$ is not definable in $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$ over $\Gamma$ it suffices by Theorem 3.3 that $\gamma ^{\operatorname {c}}$ realizes in $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$ the same quantifier-free type over $\Gamma$ as some $\gamma \in \Gamma ^{\operatorname {c}}$ with $\gamma \ne \gamma ^{\operatorname {c}}$. Take $\lambda$ with $\lambda < \lambda +1<\nu$ such that $\gamma ^{\operatorname {c}}\in \Gamma _{\lambda +1}\setminus \Gamma _{\lambda }$. Then

\[ \gamma^{\operatorname{c}} = \gamma_{\lambda}+d\alpha_{\lambda} \qquad (\gamma_{\lambda}\in \Gamma_{\lambda},\ d\in {\boldsymbol{k}}^\times). \]

Take any $\alpha \ne \alpha _{\lambda }$ in $\Gamma _{\lambda +1}^{>}$ such that $[\alpha ]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}=[\alpha _{\lambda }]_{{\boldsymbol {k}}}$. Then $\gamma ^{\operatorname {c}}\ne \gamma :=\gamma _{\lambda }+d\alpha$. Lemma 3.1 gives an automorphism $\sigma$ of $(\Gamma _{\lambda +1},\, \psi _{\lambda +1},\, P_{\lambda +1})$ over $\Gamma _{\lambda }$ with $\sigma (\alpha )=\alpha _{\lambda }$, so $\sigma (\gamma ^{\operatorname {c}})=\gamma$. Thus, $\gamma ^{\operatorname {c}}$ and $\gamma$ realize in $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }^*$ the same quantifier-free type over $\Gamma$.

A closure property of closed $H$-couples

We show here how [Reference Aschenbrenner and van den Dries1, Properties A and B] and its variant [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2, § 9.9] follow from our QE.

Let $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$ be an $H$-couple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$. We extend ${\psi \colon \Gamma ^{\ne }\to \Gamma }$ to a function $\psi \colon \Gamma _{\infty } \to \Gamma _{\infty }$ by $\psi (0)=\psi (\infty ):= \infty$. For $\alpha _1,\,\ldots,\,\alpha _n\in \Gamma$, $n\geqslant 1$, we define $\psi _{\alpha _1,\ldots,\alpha _n}\colon \Gamma _{\infty }\to \Gamma _{\infty }$ by recursion on $n$:

\[ \psi_{\alpha_1}(\gamma)\ :=\ \psi(\gamma-\alpha_1), \quad \psi_{\alpha_1,\ldots, \alpha_{n}}(\gamma)\ :=\ \psi\big(\psi_{\alpha_1,\ldots, \alpha_{n-1}}(\gamma)-\alpha_{n}\big) \text{ for }n\geqslant 2. \]

Let $D$ be a subset of an ordered abelian group $\Delta$. Call $D$ bounded if $D\subseteq [p,\,q]$ for some $p\leqslant q$ in $\Delta$, and otherwise, call $D$ unbounded. (These notions and the next one are with respect to the ambient $\Delta$.) A (convex) component of $D$ is by definition a non-empty convex subset $S$ of $\Delta$ such that $S\subseteq D$ and $S$ is maximal with these properties. The components of $D$ partition the set $D$: for $d\in D$ the unique component of $D$ containing $d$ is

\[ \big\{\gamma\in D^{\leqslant d}:\,[\gamma,d]\subseteq D\big\} \cup \big\{\gamma\in D^{\geqslant d}:\, [d,\gamma]\subseteq D\big\}. \]

Let $n\geqslant 1$, and let $\alpha$ be a sequence $\alpha _1,\,\ldots,\, \alpha _n$ from $\Gamma$. We set

\[ D_{\alpha}\ :=\ \big\{\gamma\in \Gamma:\,\psi_{\alpha}(\gamma)\ne \infty\big\}. \]

Thus,

\begin{align*} D_{\alpha}& =\Gamma\setminus \{\alpha_1\} \text{ for }n=1,\text{ and} \\ D_{\alpha}& =\big\{\gamma\in D_{\alpha'}:\,\psi_{\alpha'}(\gamma)\ne \alpha_n\big\} \text{ for }n>1\text{ and }\alpha'=\alpha_1,\ldots, \alpha_{n-1}. \end{align*}

One checks easily by induction on $n$ that for distinct $\gamma,\, \gamma '\in D_{\alpha }$,

\[ \psi_{\alpha}(\gamma)- \psi_{\alpha}(\gamma') = o(\gamma-\gamma'). \]

Let $n\geqslant 1$, let $\alpha _1,\,\ldots,\, \alpha _n\in \Gamma$, set $\alpha :=(\alpha _1,\,\ldots,\,\alpha _n)$, and let $c_1,\,\ldots,\, c_n\in {\boldsymbol {k}}$.

The next lemma is [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2, Lemma 9.9.3], generalized from ${\boldsymbol {k}}=\mathbb {Q}$ to arbitrary ${\boldsymbol {k}}$, with the same (easy) proof.

Lemma 6.2 The function

\[ \gamma\mapsto \gamma + c_1\psi_{\alpha_1}(\gamma) + \cdots + c_n\psi_{\alpha_1,\ldots,\alpha_n}(\gamma)\ :\,D_{\alpha} \to \Gamma \]

is strictly increasing. Moreover, this function has the intermediate value property on every component of $D_{\alpha }$.

Proposition 6.3 Suppose $(\Gamma,\, \psi )$ is closed, $(\Gamma ^*,\,\psi ^*)$ is an $H$-couple over ${\boldsymbol {k}}$ extending $(\Gamma,\,\psi ),$ and $\gamma \in \Gamma ^*$ is such that

\begin{align*} & \psi^*_{\alpha_1,\ldots,\alpha_n}(\gamma)\ne \infty\quad \text{(so }\psi^*_{\alpha_1,\ldots,\alpha_i}(\gamma)\ne \infty \text{ for }i=1,\ldots,n \text{)},\ \text{ and}\\ & \gamma + c_1\psi^*_{\alpha_1}(\gamma) + \cdots + c_n\psi^*_{\alpha_1,\ldots,\alpha_n}(\gamma)\in \Gamma. \end{align*}

Then $\gamma \in \Gamma$.

Proof. By extending $(\Gamma ^*,\, \psi ^*)$ we arrange it to be closed. Then by Theorem 3.3, $(\Gamma,\,\psi,\,\Psi )\preccurlyeq (\Gamma ^*,\, \psi ^*,\, \Psi ^*)$, and so we have $\beta \in \Gamma$ such that $\psi _{\alpha _1,\ldots,\alpha _n}(\beta )\ne \infty$ and

\[ \beta + c_1\psi_{\alpha_1}(\beta) + \cdots + c_n\psi_{\alpha_1,\ldots,\alpha_n}(\beta)=\gamma + c_1\psi^*_{\alpha_1}(\gamma) + \cdots + c_n\psi^*_{\alpha_1,\ldots,\alpha_n}(\gamma). \]

It remains to note that then $\beta =\gamma$ by Lemma 6.2.

7. Final remarks

In [Reference Aschenbrenner and van den Dries1], we adopted the $2$-sorted setting and “Hahn type” at the outset and only observed in its last section that much went through in a one-sorted setting without Hahn type assumption and just rational scalars. Here we have reversed this order, since our proof of Theorem 0.1 required various facts, such as Lemmas 2.7 and 4.5, about “one-sorted” closed $H$-couples over an arbitrary ordered scalar field that are not readily available in [Reference Aschenbrenner and van den Dries1].

There remain several parts in [Reference Aschenbrenner and van den Dries1] that we have not tried to cover or extend here. These concern the definable closure of an $H$-couple in an ambient closed $H$-couple, the uniqueness of $H$-closures, the well-orderedness of $\Psi$ for finitely generated $H$-couples, the weak o-minimality of closed $H$-couples, and the local o-minimality and o-minimality at infinity of models of $T_H$. We alert the reader that our terminology (and notation) concerning asymptotic couples have evolved since [Reference Aschenbrenner and van den Dries1], and are now in line with [Reference Aschenbrenner, van den Dries and van der Hoeven2], and so comparisons with the material here and in [Reference Aschenbrenner and van den Dries1] require careful attention to the exact meaning of words.

We do intend to treat some of these topics in a follow-up, since our revisit also uncovered errors in the alleged proofs of weak o-minimality and local o-minimality in [Reference Aschenbrenner and van den Dries1]. These can be corrected using the present paper, but this is not entirely a routine matter.

Competing interests

The authors declare none.

References

Aschenbrenner, M. and van den Dries, L., Closed asymptotic couples, J. Algebra 225 (2000), 309358.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aschenbrenner, M., van den Dries, L. and van der Hoeven, J., Asymptotic differential algebra and model theory of transseries, Annals of Mathematics Studies, Volume 195 (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 2017).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aschenbrenner, M., van den Dries, L. and van der Hoeven, J., Dimension in the realm of transseries, in Ordered Algebraic Structures and Related Topics (eds. F. Broglia et al. ), pp. 23–39, Contemp. Math., Volume 697 (Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, 2017).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van den Dries, L., Macintyre, A. and Marker, D., Logarithmic-exponential power series, J. London Math. Soc. 56 (1997), 417434.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pynn-Coates, N., Model theory of differential-Henselian pre- $H$-fields, arXiv:1910.12171Google Scholar
Pynn-Coates, N., On asymptotic valued differential fields with small derivation, PhD dissertation, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, 2020Google Scholar
Rosenlicht, M., Differential valuations, Pacific J. Math. 86 (1980), 301319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar