No CrossRef data available.
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 25 March 2011
Is listening to (purely instrumental) music like looking through a kaleidoscope? Formalists contend that music is meaningless. Most music theorists concede that this austere thesis is surprisingly close to the truth. Nevertheless, they refute formalism with a little band of diffusely referential phenomena, such as musical quotation, onomatopoeia, exemplification, and leitmotifs. These curiosities ought to be pressed into a new campaign against assumptions that vagueness can only arise in the semantically lush setting of language. Just as the discovery of extremophilic bacteria led biologists to revise their opinions about the scope and preconditions of life, the marginal forms of reference that survive in the semantic desert of absolute music should lead philosophers to revise their assumptions much about scope and preconditions of vagueness.
1 Russell, Bertrand, ‘Vagueness’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy and Psychology 1, (1923), 84–92. Russell extends vagueness beyond language to maps and photographs. He does not distinguish between vagueness as the possession of borderline cases (as in ‘thirty-ish’) and vagueness as underspecificity (as in ‘thirty-something’ which encompasses a wide but precise interval)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
2 Lerdahl, Fred and Ray, Jackendoff, A Generative Theory of Tonal Music (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1996). A wrong note is like a grammatical error. Just as a native speaker can identify a solecism in a sentence he never heard before, members of a concert audience can identify a wrong note in a novel compositionGoogle Scholar.
3 Davies, Stephen, Musical Meaning and Expression (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994)Google Scholar chapter 1.
4 Levinson, Jerrold, ‘The Concept of Music’, in his Music, Art, and Metaphysics (Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press, 1990), 267–78Google Scholar, 272.
5 Hamilton, AndyAesthetics and Music (New York, NY: Continuum Press, 2007), 40–55Google Scholar.
6 Cloarec-Heiss, Frances, ‘From natural language to drum language: An economical encoding procedure in Banda-Linda, Central African Republic’ Language diversity and cognitive representations edited by Fuchs, Catherine, Robert, Stéphane, (Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishers, 1999)Google Scholar.
7 Smith, Adam, Philosophical Subjects (London, 1795)Google Scholar, 133.
8 Kivy, Peter, Sound and Semblance (Princeton University Press, 1984), 101Google Scholar.
9 Zahavi, Amotz, ‘Mate selection – a selection for a handicap’ Journal of Theoretical Biology 53 (1975), 205–214CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.
10 Pasnau, Robert, ‘What is Sound? Philosophical Quarterly 50 (1999), 309–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
11 Scruton, Roger, The Aesthetics of Music (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997) 221Google Scholar.
12 Walton, Kendall, Mimesis as Make-Believe (Cambridge, Mass., MIT Press, 1990), 340Google Scholar.
13 Perris, Arnold, Music as Propaganda: Art to persuade, art to control (Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood Press, 1985)Google Scholar.
14 Sousa, John Philip, Marching Along (Waterville, Ohio: Integrity Press, 1994), 358Google Scholar.
15 Sorensen, Roy, ‘Vagueness within the Language of Thought’, Philosophical Quarterly 41 (1991), 389–413CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
16 Fine, Kit, ‘Vagueness, truth and logic’, Syntheses 54 (1975): 235–259Google Scholar, 282. Reprinted in Vagueness: A Reader, Keefe, Rosanna and Smith, Peter (eds.), (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1996), 119–150Google Scholar.
17 Wright, Crispin, ‘Language Mastery and the Sorites Paradox’ in Evans and McDowell (eds.) Truth and Meaning (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1976), 223–247Google Scholar.
18 Soames, Scott, Understanding Truth (New York: Oxford, 1999), 206–212CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
19 Brown, Steven, ‘The “Musilanguage” Model of Music Evolution’ in Wallin, N. L., Merker, B., and Brown, S. (eds.) The Origins of Music. (Cambridge: The MIT Press, 1999), 271–301Google Scholar.
20 Williamson, Timothy, ‘Truth and Borderline Cases’ in Korta and Larrazabal (eds.) Truth, rationality, cognition, and music (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2004), 45–66CrossRefGoogle Scholar; 54.
21 Freud, Sigmund, ‘The Unconscious’ in The Pelican Freud Library (Hammondsworth: Penguin Books, 1984) vol. 11, 190–191Google Scholar.
22 London, Justin, ‘Musical and Linguistic Speech Acts’, The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 54 (1996), 49–64CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
23 Schwartz, Stephen P., ‘Soritic thinking, vagueness, and weakness of will’, New Ideas in Psychology 27 (2009), 18–31CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
24 Quinn, Warren, ‘The puzzle of the self-torturer’, Philosophical Studies 59 (1990), 79–90CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
25 Shepherd, Roger N, ‘Circularity in Judgments of Relative Pitch’, Journal of the Acoustical Society of America 36 (1964), 2346–2353CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
26 Huron, David, Sweet Anticipation: Music and the Psychology of Expectation (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2006)Google Scholar.
27 van Fraassen, Bas, ‘On a Kantian Conception of Language’, in Martin, R. M. (ed.) The Paradox of the Liar (New Haven: Yale University Press 1970), 59–66Google Scholar.