Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-24T17:38:37.919Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Theodicy and Animal Pain

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 January 2009

Peter Harrison
Affiliation:
University of Queensland
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

The existence of evil is compatible with the existence of God, most theists would claim, because evil either results from the activities of free agents, or it contributes in some way toward their moral development. According to the ‘free-will defence’, evil and suffering are necessary consequences of free-will. Proponents of the ‘soul-making argument’—a theodicy with a different emphasis—argue that a universe which is imperfect will nurture a whole range of virtues in a way impossible either in a perfect world, or in a totally evil one. The pain of animals is widely thought to constitute a major difficulty for both of these accounts, for if we ask whether the only evils present in the world result directly from the free actions of created agents, or contribute in some way to ‘soul-making’ of such agents, we are bound to admit that, on the face of it, much animal pain does not.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1989

References

1 Modern accounts of these theodicies may be found in Pantinga, Alvin, God and Other Minds (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1967) chs. 5 and 6Google Scholar; and Hick, John, Evil and the God of Love (London: Fontana, 1968).Google Scholar

2 Descartes, René, A Discourse on Method, trans. Veitch, John (London: Dent, 1957) pt. v (44ff.)Google Scholar; Letter CXCII (to Mersenne), in Oeuvres de Descartes, Adam, Charles and Tannery, Paul (eds) (Paris: L. Cerf, 18971913) III, 85.Google Scholar

3 Bayle, Pierre, ‘Rorarius’, note ‘B’, Historical and Critical Dictionary, selected and trans, by Popkin, Richard (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1965) 215fGoogle Scholar. In remark ‘E’ of the article ‘Pereira’, Bayle began to set out a history of views on the nature of the soul of animals. This history was completed in the article ‘Rorarius’.

4 Bayle, , ‘Rorarius’, note ‘C’Google Scholar, ibid., 220.

5 See, e.g., Lewis, C. S., The Problem of Pain (London: Fontana, 1957), 121124Google Scholar; Mascall, E. L., Christian Theology and Natural Science (London: Longmans, Green and Co., 1956) 301302Google Scholar; Webb, D. B., Why Does God Permit Evil? (London: Burns, Oates and Washbourne, 1941) 3335.Google Scholar

6 See, e.g., Lewis, , The Problem of Pain, 121124Google Scholar; Plantinga, Alvin, God and Other Minds 149 f.Google Scholar

7 Swinburne, Richard, ‘The Problem of Evil’, Contemporary Philosophy of Religion, Cahan, Steven M. and Shatz, David, (eds) (Oxford University Press, 1982), 12 f.Google Scholar

8 We ask the question: What is it by virtue of which we differ from the animals? The answer is given: Intelligence. But what is ‘Intelligence’? Intelligence is defined. But animal X displays intelligence. Oh, perhaps it is the ability to use language, then. But Lucy the chimpanzee was able to learn American Sign Language. Could the difference be Creativity… ? And so the original distinction is forgotten in our concern to label an attribute which accounts for our being different.

9 White, J. C. and Sweet, W. H., Pain: Its Mechanisms and Neurosurgical Control (Springfield, Ill.: Charles C. Thomas, 1955) 68.Google Scholar

10 Leriche, Reńe, The Surgery of Pain, ed. and trans, by Young, Archibald, (Baltimore: Williams and Wilkins, 1939) 23Google Scholar; Buytendijk, F. J. J., Pain: Its Modes and Functions (University of Chicago Press, 1962) 40.Google Scholar

11 On chronic insensitivity to pain and its consequences, see Melzak, Ronald, The Puzzle of Pain (New York: Basic Books, 1973) 1516.Google Scholar

12 See ibid., 85.

13 Noordenbos, W., Pain: Problems Pertaining to the Transmission of Nerve Impulses Which Give Rise to Pain (New York: Elsevier Publishing Co., 1959), 176.Google Scholar

14 McFarland, David, ‘Pain’, The Oxford Companion to Animal Behaviour, MacFarland, David (ed.) (Oxford University Press, 1981), 439.Google Scholar

15 See, e.g., Hick, John, Evil and the God of Love (London: Fontana, 1968), 346 f.Google Scholar; Serjeant, Richard, The Spectrum of Pain (London: Hart-Davis, 1969) 72Google Scholar; Peter, Singer, Animal Liberation (London: Jonathan Cape, 1976) 13 f.Google Scholar

16 Aristotle, , Nicomachean Ethics, Bk. II, ch. iiiGoogle Scholar; Bk. III, ch. xi; de Spinoza, Baruch, Ethics III, prop. lvGoogle Scholar; Ryle, Gilbert, The Concept of Mind (New York: Barnes and Noble, 1949), 203.Google Scholar

17 Melzak, , The Puzzle of Pain, 22Google Scholar. Cf. Dick-Read, Grantly, Childbirth Without Fear (New York: Dell, 1962).Google Scholar

18 Clark, J. W. and Bindra, D., ‘Individual Differences in Pain Thresholds’, Canadian Journal of Psychology 10 (1956), 6981.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

19 Melzak, , The Puzzle of Pain, 2931.Google Scholar

20 Hill, Harris et al. , ‘Studies on Anxiety Associated with Anticipation of Pain: Effects of Morphine’, AMA Archives of Neurology and Psychiatry, 67 (1952), 612619CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Cf. Beecher, Henry K., Measurement of Subjective Responses: Quantitative Effects of Drugs (New York: Oxford University Press, 1959), passim.Google Scholar

21 Bakan, David, Disease, Pain and Sacrifice: Toward a Psychology of Suffering (University of Chicago Press, 1968) 70.Google Scholar

22 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Zettel (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1970), Nos. 533, 534 (94 ff.)Google Scholar. Cf. Illich, Ivan: ‘The act of suffering pain always has a [sic] historical dimension’, Limits to Medicine (Ringwood: Penguin, 1977) 148.Google Scholar

23 Wittgenstein once asked what difference it would make if anaesthetics only made us forget pain. This example is developed from that question.

24 If I read him correctly, this is a line of argument which C. S. Lewis also adopts. See The Problem of Pain, 119f.Google Scholar

25 Mackintosh, Nicholas, ‘Learning’, Oxford Companion to Animal Behaviour, 337.Google Scholar