Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-gb8f7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T05:10:29.486Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Philosophy in France

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 February 2009

Extract

History and Legend are, Professor Robin believes, traditionally misconceived in being conceived as in conflict. To write history is either to destroy utterly the claim of some legend to be veridical, or else to rediscover, behind what is imaginary or fabulous in it, indications of what the facts really were. Such is the accredited view. But, asks M. Robin, is not legend, on the contrary, a positive element in history? And he answers in effect that nowhere is legend more regular, indeed more necessary, than in its contribution to the history of philosophy, ancient and modern. This history has a wholly original character. It does not resemble the history of the sciences; for this relates either the checkmates in research—instructive to be sure, but dead for future science—or else its victories—equally instructive, though only their results survive. Nor does it resemble literary history; for even if this be accompanied by evaluatory criticism, seldom is interpretation of doctrine admitted. Interpreting a philosophy is seizing not only its literal sense, but above all its import and efficacy. It is a continuously creative and reflective activity which unceasingly quickens the materials on which it reflects. But since what is called objectivity cannot be attained by the historian of philosophy except by shutting his eyes to the limits of his powers, he must candidly confess—and without admitting that the confession impairs the value of his effort—that objectivity cannot be his chief end. No great philosophy can really be considered dead, its sincere and sympathetic evocation is always possible. The history of philosophy is philosophy; it is philosophy philosophizing on its past efforts, and contemplating itself in the perenniality of its changing existence.

Type
Philosophical Survey
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1936

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 86 note 1 Robin, L., “L'histoire et la légende de la philosophie,” Revue philosophique, 60e année, Nos. 9 and 10, 1935. Pp. 161175.Google Scholar

page 86 note 2 Robin, Leon, La Theorie Platonicienne de l'Amour, nouvelle édition. Paris: Alcan, 1933. 30 Fr. Pp. 229.Google ScholarPlaton; Œuvres complètes. Tome IV. 3e partie—Phédre. Texte établi et traduit par Robin, L., Collection des Universités de France. Paris: Socété d'EditionLes Belles Lettres,” 1933. Pp. clxxxv + 96. 30 Fr.Google Scholar

page 87 note 1 Schuhl, P. M., Essai sur la Formation de la Pensée grecque: Introduction historique à une étvde de la philosophe platonicienne. Paris: Alcan, 1934. Pp. 466. 50 Fr.Google Scholar

page 89 note 1 Schuhl, P. M., Platon et l’ Art de son temps (Arts plastiques). Paris: Alcan, 1933. Pp. 123. to Fr.Google Scholar

page 90 note 1 Rey, A., La Science dans I'Antiquité. I. La Science orientate avant les Grecs, 1930. Pp. xvii + 495. 30 Fr.Google Scholar II. La Jeunesse de la science grecque. Paris: La Renaissance du Livre, 1933. Pp. xvii + 537. 30 Fr.Google Scholar

page 90 note 2 Rey, A., Les Mathematiques en Grèce au milieu du ve siècle, “Exposés d'Histoire et Philosophie des Sciences,” No. 1. Paris: Hermann et Cie, 1935. Pp. 92. 18 Fr.Google Scholar