Article contents
Moral Scepticism and Moral Conduct
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 30 January 2009
Extract
For a period in the middle of the present century moral philosophy was dominated by the debate between prescriptivists and descriptivists. Prescriptivists proclaimed a gap between ‘is’ and ‘ought’, between facts and values, and cheerfully accepted the sceptical consequence that morals, and values generally, could not be objects of knowledge.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1984
References
1 The labels are taken from Hare, R. M.. See Freedom and Reason (Oxford University Press, 1963Google Scholar), 84, and ‘Descriptivism’, The Is/Ought Question, Hudson, W. D. (ed.) (London: Macmillan, 1969), 240–258. By ‘prescriptivists’ I mean to include those writers usually called ‘emotivists’.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
2 Stevenson, C. L., Ethics and Language (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1943)Google Scholar; Hare, R. M., The Language of Morals (Oxford University Press, 1952).Google Scholar
3 Searle, John R., ‘How to Derive “Ought” from “Is” ’, The Philosophical Review 73 (January 1964), 43–58.Google Scholar
4 Philippa, Foot, ‘Moral Arguments’, Mind 67, No. 268 (October 1958), 502–513.Google Scholar
5 Philippa, Foot, ‘Goodness and Choice’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 35 (1961).Google Scholar
6 Stevenson, C. L., ‘The Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms’, Mind 46, No. 181 (January 1937), 16.Google Scholar
7 The Philosophical Review 81, No. 3 (July 1972), 305–316.
8 Ibid. 311.
9 Ibid. 315.
10 Popper, K. R., The Open Society and its Enemies, Vol. I (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1945), Ch. 5.Google Scholar
11 For an expression of worries along these lines see Paton's, H. J. contribution to the symposium ‘The Emotive Theory of Ethics’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 22 (1948), 119–122.Google Scholar
12 Whether I will do A is, of course, another matter.
- 1
- Cited by