Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dlnhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T06:15:18.885Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Moore's Commonplace Book

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 February 2009

Morris Lazerowitz
Affiliation:
Smith College.

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Discussion
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1964

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 165 note 4 The Commonplace Book of G. E. Moore 1919-1953. Edited by Gasimir, Lewy. Muirhead Library of Philosophy. London: George Allen and Unwin, Ltd., New York: The Macmillan Co. Pp. xvii+410. Price 42s.Google Scholar

page 166 note 1 George Edward Moore 1873-1958’, Proceedings of the British Academy, Vol. 67, p. 300.Google Scholar

page 166 note 1 Ibid., p. 301.

page 168 note 1 The first formula results from simple substitution on ‘q. ⊃.p ν q’ and the second, in Lewis' notation written ‘p. ≺.q ν ∼ q’, is argued for in Lewis and Langford's Symbolic Logic, p. 251.

page 168 note 2 Moore sometimes surprised his friends with the unexpected. Some of us who enjoyed musical sessions with him expected him to have a strong preference for Bach as against such romantics as Schumann and Hugo Wolf, but it was just the other way round.

page 170 note 1 It is interesting that in Some Main Problems of Philosophy, p. 38, Moore had said: ‘It seems very probable … that none of the sizes and shapes seen were the size or the shape of the real envelope’.Google Scholar

page 171 note 1 ‘A Defence of Common Sense’, Philosophical Papers, p. 56.Google Scholar

page 172 note 1 Language, Truth and Logic, 2nd edition, p. 88.Google Scholar

page 173 note 1 In one way or another the two so-called paradoxes of material implication, ‘q. ⊃.p ⊃ q’ and ‘ ∼ p.p ⊃ q’, tend to be represented as exhibiting astonishing properties of ‘if p, q’ rather than uninteresting properties of disjunction artificially freed from conditions of relevance.