Article contents
Foresight and Responsibility
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 30 January 2009
Extract
Where a man foresaw that through its consequences his action would violate a law, is he for that reason to be judged responsible for the violation of the law? The principle that such a man is responsible, and thus that foresight is sufficient for responsibility, has long been accepted in both legal and moral theory. But in recent years anxieties about this principle have been expressed by both philosophers and lawyers. What one commonly finds in older books, both legal and ethical, is the thesis that foresight is proof of intention. Given that intention is sufficient for responsibility, this thesis has as consequence the principle that foresight is sufficient for responsibility, but it is only required by that principle if one wants to keep the view that intention is also necessary for responsibility in all cases where negligence is not involved. Miss Anscombe (op. cit., note i) made the extraordinary suggestion that this thesis that foresight is proof of intention originates with Sidgwick, and she took him severely to task on this account; indeed, she even implied that Sidgwick's introduction of this thesis is the source of the shallowness of ‘modern’ moral philosophy. While it is true that Sidgwick did endorse this thesis, in a somewhat qualified manner, he was only following an established tradition of utilitarian thought to which the thesis belongs (not because it is specifically utilitarian in content but because the utilitarians Bentham and Austin were among the first writers to try to articulate clearly the principles of responsibility). Thus this thesis occurs in John Austin's 1828 lectures on Jurisprudence (lecture XIX) and the best early discussion of it is to be found in Bentham's Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (Chs. VIII, IX). Bentham, it is true, introduces a distinction between ‘directly intentional consequences’ and ‘obliquely intentional consequences’ which we might describe as a distinction between consequences that are intended and those that are foreseen but not intended. But for Bentham, foresight is proof of intention, and thus for him obliquely intentional consequences are intended: ‘Advisedness with respect to the circumstances, if clear from the mis-supposal of any preventive circumstance, extends the intentionality from the act to its consequences’ (Ch. IX, 10).
- Type
- Articles
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1979
References
1 Especially MissAnscombe, in ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’, Philosophy 33, No. 124 (01 1958)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and Kenny, A. in ‘Intention and Purpose in Law’, in Essays in Legal Philosophy, Summers, R. (ed.) (Oxford: Blackwell, 1968)Google Scholar. Kenny continues his argument in Chapter IV of Will, Freedom and Power (Oxford: Blackwell, 1975)Google Scholar, and in ‘Intention and Mens Rea in Murder’, in Law, Morality and Society, Hacker, P. and Raz, J. (eds) (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977).Google Scholar
2 Cf. Hyam v. D.P.P. (1975)Google Scholar A.C.55 and the Criminal Law Revision Committee's ‘Working Paper on Offences against the Person’ (London: HMSO, 08 1976).Google Scholar
3 Cf. Methods of Ethics (London: Macmillan, 1962), 60, 202.Google Scholar
4 Cf. Hogan, B. ‘Funeral in Dublin’, Criminal Law Review (08 1970)Google Scholar, where a similar more recent case is also described.
5 The Times, 28 04 1868.Google Scholar
6 Cf. Williams, G., The Criminal Law (London: Stevens, 1961), §13.Google Scholar
7 This interpretation is much stressed by Kenny, in ‘Intention and Mens Rea in Murder’, op. cit., note 1, 167–168.Google Scholar
8 Op. cit., note 1.
9 Cf. Sacks, O., Awakenings (London: Duckworth, 1973), 209 ff.Google Scholar
10 Op. cit., note 9.
11 Op. cit., note 1, 11.
12 ‘Intention and Purpose in Law’, op. cit., note 1, 160.Google Scholar
13 Summa Theologiae 1a 2ae 73, 8Google Scholar; transl. Gilby, (London: Eyre and Spottis-woode, 1969), 83–85.Google Scholar
14 Will, Freedom and Power, op. cit., note 1, 67.Google Scholar
15 Op. cit., note 2.
16 They imply (§43) that these cases will be covered by another new offence which they propose, causing death with intent to cause serious injury. But this must be a mistake.
17 ‘Intention and Mens Rea in Murder’, op. cit., note 1, 172–173.Google Scholar
18 Williams, G., The Mental Element in Crime (Jerusalem: Magnes Press, 1965).Google Scholar
19 Cf. Hailsham, Lord in Hyam v. D.P.P. 74E–F.Google Scholar
20 Casey, J., ‘Actions and Consequences’, in Morality and Moral Reasoning Casey, J. (ed.) (London: Methuen, 1971), 192.Google Scholar
21 Stephen, J. F., History of Criminal Law, iii (London: Macmillan, 1883), 8.Google Scholar
- 4
- Cited by