Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7czq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-29T02:18:20.679Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Relatively Objective Morality

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 January 2009

F. Gerald Downing
Affiliation:
Norther Ordination Course, Manchester

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Discussion
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1986

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Harrison, Bernard, ‘Moral Judgment, Action and Emotion’, Philosophy 59, No. 229 (07 1984), 297321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

2 Downing, F. Gerald, ‘Ways of Deriving “Ought” from “Is’’, Philosophical Quarterly 22, No. 88 (07 1972), 234247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar Though, like Harrison, , I found useful Julius Kovesi, Moral Notions (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1967), I was rather more engaged with John R. Searle, Speech Acts (Cambridge University Press, 1969), and his preferred term ‘institution’.Google Scholar

3 Whiteley, C. H., ‘The Justification of Morality’, Philosophy 57, No. 222 (10 1982), 435451.CrossRefGoogle Scholar But I would note also Iris, Murdoch, ‘Vision and Choice in Morality’, in Christian Ethics and Contemporary Philosophy, Ramsey, Ian T. (ed.) (London: SCM Press 1966), 195218, protesting against philosophers' attempts to homogenize morality. There are yet more complicating factors that need to be taken into account, not least the tendency to have one set of conventions for polite conversation and other sets for use. Hypocrisy, weakness and wickedness affect our perceptions of the moral ‘field’, and not just our actions.Google Scholar