Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-18T09:16:01.717Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Recent Critics of Mill's Qualitative Hedonism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 September 2016

Abstract

Two recent critics of Mill's qualitative hedonism, Michael Hauskeller and Kristin Schaupp, argue that Mill's distinction between higher and lower pleasures was largely unsuccessful. They allege that Mill failed to demonstrate that some pleasures are lexically preferred to others, and indeed that this can be shown false by the fact that most people would not renounce supposedly lower pleasures, such as chocolate or sex, even for greater amounts of higher pleasures, such as reading or opera. I respond that many of these criticisms rest on uncharitable assumptions or interpretations of Mill's position. We need not suppose that Mill was even trying to do the things he supposedly failed to do. However, considering these objections may lead us to a more plausible interpretation of Mill's views, according to which the quality of pleasures, along with their quantity, contributes towards happiness. There is no need to suppose that ‘higher pleasures’ must be lexically preferred to lower ones, or even to be dogmatic about which pleasures are higher.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 For example, Martin, Rex, ‘A Defence of Mill's Qualitative Hedonism’, Philosophy 47 (1972), 140–51CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and West, Henry R., ‘Mill's Qualitative Hedonism’, Philosophy 51 (1976), 97101 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Saunders, Ben, ‘J. S. Mill's Conception of Utility’, Utilitas 22 (2010), 5269 CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Saunders, Ben, ‘Reinterpreting the Qualitative Hedonism Advanced by J.S. Mill’, Journal of Value Inquiry 45 (2011), 187201 CrossRefGoogle Scholar and Mill's Conception of Happiness’, in Macleod, C. and Miller, D. E. (eds) A Companion to Mill (Wiley-Blackwell, 2017), 313327 Google Scholar.

3 Hauskeller, Michael, ‘No Philosophy for Swine: John Stuart Mill on the Quality of Pleasures’, Utilitas 23 (2011), 428–46CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 428.

4 Schaupp, Kristin, ‘Books before Chocolate? The Insufficiency of Mill's Evidence for Higher Pleasures’, Utilitas 25 (2013), 266–76CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 268.

5 That falsehoods can lead to a better appreciation of the truth is, of course, part of Mill's case for free discussion. See On Liberty, reprinted in Robson, J. M. (ed.) The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol. XVIII (Toronto: Toronto University Press, 1977)Google Scholar, 243ff.

6 Utilitarianism, reprinted in Robson, J. M. (ed.) The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol. X (Toronto: Toronto University Press, 1969), 207Google Scholar.

7 Op. cit. note 6, 208.

8 Op. cit. note 6, 222.

9 Op. cit. note 6, 235.

10 Op. cit. note 6, 259.

11 Op. cit. note 5, 252ff.

12 Op. cit. note 6, 210.

13 E.g. Ryan, Alan, J.S. Mill (London: Routledge, 1974), 97 Google Scholar, and Crisp, Roger, Mill on Utilitarianism (London: Routledge, 1997), 23 Google Scholar.

14 Op. cit. note 6, 210.

15 Op. cit. note 6, 211.

16 Op. cit. note 6, 210–11.

17 Op. cit. note 6, 211.

18 Op. cit. note 4, 267.

19 Cf. Nozick, Robert, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1974), 42–5Google Scholar.

20 Op. cit. note 6, 235ff.

21 Op. cit. note 6, 210.

22 Thomson, Judith Jarvis, ‘A Defense of Abortion’, Philosophy & Public Affairs 1 (1971), 4766 Google Scholar.

23 See ‘Bentham’, reprinted in Robson, J. M. (ed.) The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol. X (Toronto: Toronto University Press, 1969)Google Scholar. Mill criticizes Bentham's narrow view of human nature, 92–6, and remarks on Bentham's distrust of poetry, CW X, 113–14.

For Mill's own appreciation of poetry, see Autobiography, reprinted in Robson, J. M. and Stillinger, J. (eds) The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol. I (Toronto: Toronto University Press, 1981), 148–53Google Scholar. See also Anderson, Elizabeth, ‘John Stuart Mill and Experiments in Living’, Ethics 102 (1991), 426 CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 17–18, and McKinnell, Liz, ‘“A Medicine for my State of Mind”: The Role of Wordsworth in John Stuart Mill's Moral and Psychological Development’, Utilitas 27 (2015), 4360 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

24 Bronaugh, Richard, ‘The Quality in Pleasures’, Philosophy 49 (1974), 320–22CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 321.

25 Op. cit. note 6, 211.

26 Op. cit. note 4, 276.

27 Op. cit. note 6, 214.

28 Op. cit. note 3, 431ff.

29 Op. cit. note 6, 211.

30 Millgram, Elijah, ‘Mill's Proof of the Principle of Utility’, Ethics 110 (2000), 282310 CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 297. For a critical response, see Miller, Dale E., ‘On Millgram on Mill’, Utilitas 16 (2004), 96108 CrossRefGoogle Scholar, especially 107.

31 Op. cit. note 3, 433.

32 Op. cit. note 6, 213.

33 Op. cit. note 6, 212.

34 Op. cit. note 3, 441.

35 Op. cit. note 3, 431.

36 This example comes from Schmidt-Petri, Christoph, ‘On an Interpretation of Mill's Qualitative Utilitarianism’, Prolegomena 5 (2006), 165–77Google Scholar, at 166.

37 This example is used in Schmidt-Petri, Christoph, ‘Mill on Quality and Quantity’, The Philosophical Quarterly 53 (2003), 102–4CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and Ben Saunders, ‘J. S. Mill's Conception of Utility’, op. cit. note 2.

38 Op. cit. note 4, 274.

39 Op. cit. note 6, 211.

40 Gettier, Edmund L., ‘Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?’, Analysis 23 (1963), 121–3CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

41 Of course, the committee's preferences may be affected by institutional incentives. For instance, as of 2014, the UK's periodic ‘Research Excellence Framework’ (REF), which both allocates government research funding and features in numerous league tables, considers only four outputs from each researcher in each assessment period. For this purpose, someone with four 3* articles and nothing else is preferable to someone with three 3* articles and any number of 2* articles. However, given that 2* work is still ‘recognised internationally in terms of originality, significance and rigour’ (http://www.ref.ac.uk/panels/assessmentcriteriaandleveldefinitions/), it is not obvious that the former is a better philosopher, even though they score more highly in the REF.

42 Op. cit. note 6, 211.

43 Op. cit. note 6, 211.

44 Op. cit. note 37, 103.

45 Op. cit. note 6, 211.

46 Op. cit. note 6, 214.

47 Op. cit. note 4, 270. The example is originally from Anderson, op. cit. note 23, 9.

48 Op. cit. note 4, 272–3.

49 Op. cit. note 6, 215, emphasis added.

50 Although his defence of individual freedom also allows for this; no one should be forced to experience a variety of pleasures, if they choose to devote themselves as wholly as possible to one. Although, for an account of Mill's harm principle that permits some interference with self-regarding choices, see Ben Saunders, ‘Reformulating Mill's Harm Principle’, Mind (forthcoming).

51 See Anderson, op. cit. note 23, and Muldoon, Ryan, ‘Expanding the Justificatory Framework of Mill's Experiments in Living’, Utilitas 27 (2015), 179–94CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

52 Cf. op. cit. note 5, 263.

53 Op. cit. note 6, 211.

54 Op. cit. note 6, 211.

55 Op. cit. note 3, 434.

56 Op. cit. note 3, 438.

57 Op. cit. note 3, 442.

58 E.g. Kamm, Josephine, John Stuart Mill in Love (London: Gordon & Cremonesi, 1977), 3943 Google Scholar. Kamm claims it is the ‘accepted conclusion’ that Mill and Harriet were ‘not lovers in the full sense of the word’ (39) and that ‘it seems almost certain that they were not’ ‘man and wife in the full sense of the term’ (42). She also suggests that Mill may have been impotent (41). I thank Helen McCabe, who disagrees with Kamm's conclusions, for comments and suggestions on this point.

59 Op. cit. note 6, 213.

60 Op. cit. note 6, 211.

61 It is worth noting that Harriet Taylor regarded sex as manifesting what is highest and best in human nature; see McCabe, HelenHarriet Taylor Mill’ in Macleod, C. and Miller, D. E. (eds) A Companion to Mill (Wiley-Blackwell, 2017), 112125 Google Scholar, at 119.

62 Op. cit. note 6, 211.

63 Op. cit. note 4, 272.

64 Op. cit. note 6, 211–2.

65 Op. cit. note 3, 445–6. Hauskeller appears to treat ‘pleasure’ and ‘happiness’ as interchangeable, but Mill would insist that the fool's life – even if more pleasant – is not actually happier, only more content (op. cit. note 6, 212). The truly happy life is the one we should want for ourselves, which may be the more dignified or nobler one. Cf. Finnis, John's characterization of happiness as signifying a fullness of life, in Natural Law & Natural Rights, 2nd edition (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 96 Google Scholar.

66 Op. cit. note 6, 211.

67 Op. cit. note 6, 210.

68 Cf. Crisp, Roger, ‘Hedonism Reconsidered’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (2006), 619–45CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 622–3.

69 I thank Dale Miller and Chris Macleod for stimulating me to revisit these issues, and for their comments on related earlier work, Helen McCabe for discussions of Mill's relationship with Harriet, and Chris Armstrong for helpful prompting.