Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-mlc7c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-19T01:30:56.212Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Philosophy and Psychiatry

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 February 2009

Extract

I Am grateful for the honour of being invited to give the second Manson Lecture. Dr. Manson believed that the study of sick people leads into the widest fields of thought, but that increasing specialization within medicine diverts the doctor from seeing man and his nature whole: the chief question seems to be (he wrote in 1930), “whether medicine is in the bondship of practice, whether it is a skilled art, or whether it can emerge to give its own contribution to abstract thought and philosophy.” Indeed, pleading with doctors to join this Institute of Philosophy, he declared that medicine should be the most philosophic of the professions. In this he was reviving an ancient claim: the arguments for it have lately been restated with much Aristotelian piety by Scott Buchanan. Now here I find myself in a difficulty at the outset: I am to speak of the relationship between philosophy and medicine, at a lecture founded by a passionate believer in their conjunction, yet I am engaged in a particular branch of medicine which was for longer than any other preoccupied with philosophy and dependent on it, but had so little profit from its fidelity that it reckons progress from the time when it struggled away from this allegiance. Psychiatry has not been able to refrain since then from many a backward glance at the older philosophy she once swore by, and she has been much influenced by the philosophies of later times: she has—doubtless in punishment for her defection—become entangled now and then in bad, unrecognized philosophy of her own making. She has, at all events, never achieved more than a temporary indifference to philosophic thought.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1949

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 99 note 1 British Medical Journal, 1930, No. 2, p. 266Google Scholar.

page 100 note 1 Allgemeine Psychopathologie, Jaspers, von Karl, 3te Auflage, Berlin, 1923, p. 12CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

page 101 note 1 A History of Medical Psychology, by Zilboorg, Gregory, London, 1941, p. 274Google Scholar.

page 102 note 1 Versuch über die Krankheiten des Kopfes, 1764Google Scholar.

page 103 note 1 Der Streit der Facultäten in drei Abschnitten, 1798. Abschnitt, Dritter. § 1 and 4Google Scholar.

page 103 note 2 Discours de la Méthode, Descartes, Quatrième Partie.

page 103 note 3 Ibid.

page 104 note 1 Principles of Psychology, by James, Wm., vol. 2, p. 284Google Scholar.

page 104 note 2 Ibid., vol. 2, p. 297.

page 104 note 3 Essay on Human Understanding, Book IV, Chap. 2, § 1.

page 105 note 1 Essay on Human Understanding, Book IV, Chap. 2, § 1.

page 105 note 2 Ibid., Book IV, Chap. 19, § 8.

page 105 note 3 Mind, 1945, No. 54, p. 138Google Scholar.

page 106 note 1 L'Intuition Délirante, Targowla, R. et Dublineau, J., Paris, 1931, p. 65Google Scholar.

page 106 note 2 Jour. Abn. and Soc. Psychol., 1947, No. 42, p. 470Google Scholar.

page 109 note 1 Personality, by Allport, G. W., London, 1937, P. 159Google Scholar

page 112 note 1 Journal of the American Medical Association, 1915Google Scholar.

page 113 note 1 The Biological Basis of Individuality, by Loeb, Leo, Springfield, 1945, P. 654CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

page 116 note 1 La Méthode Psychoanalytique et la Doctrine Freudienne, Paris, 1936, Tome 2, P. 454Google Scholar.