Article contents
The Neurophilosophy of Pain
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 30 January 2009
Extract
The ability to feel pain is a property of human beings that seems to be based entirely in our biological natures and to place us squarely within the animal kingdom. Yet the experience of pain is often used as an example of a mental attribute with qualitative properties that defeat attempts to identify mental events with physiological mechanisms. I will argue that neurophysiology and psychology help to explain the interwoven biological and subjective features of pain and recommend a view of pain which differs in important respects from the one most commonly accepted.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1991
References
1 Kripke, S., ‘Identity and necessity’, in Philosophy as it is, Honderich, T. & Burnyeat, M. (eds) Penguin, 1979.Google Scholar
2 Dennett, D. C., Brainstorms (Brighton: Harvester, 1981), 225.Google Scholar
3 Ibid., 226.
4 A ‘mentalist’ holds that we can tell a coherent and genuinely explanatory mental story about mental phenomena.
5 Mountcastle, V. B., Medical Physiology (12th ed.) St Louis: Mosby, 1968, 1425.Google Scholar
6 Ibid., 1444.
7 I have attacked this dogma in ‘Consciousness and Brain Function’, Philosophical Psychology (1988), 1 325–339.Google Scholar
8 Mountcastle, V. B., Medical Physiology, 1445.Google Scholar
9 Truex, R. and Carpenter, M., Human Neuroanatomy (6th ed.), (Baltimore: Williams & Wilkins, 1969), 588.Google Scholar
10 ‘Pain and Mood’, in Brain and Mind, Wolstenholme, G. (ed.) (Amsterdam: CIBA, 1979), 327.Google Scholar
11 Melzack, R., ‘The Perception of Pain’, in Physiological Psychology, Thompson, R. F. (ed.) (San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1976).Google Scholar
12 Dr Robert Twycross, Michael Sobell House, personal communication.
13 Wall, P., ‘The Three Phases of Evil: The Relation of Injury to Pain’, in Brain and Mind, op. cit., 300.Google Scholar
14 Crow, T. J., in ‘Pain and Mood’, op. cit., 327.Google Scholar
15 Melzack, R., op. cit., 223.Google Scholar
16 Melzack, R., op. cit., 223.Google Scholar
17 ‘Pain and Mood’, op. cit., 325.Google Scholar
18 Wittgenstein, L., Philosophical Investigations (Tr. Anscombe, G. E. M.) (Oxford: Blackwell, 1953), No. 257.Google Scholar
19 Philosophical Investigations, op. cit., No. 244.
20 Philosophical Investigations, op. cit., No. 257.
21 Philosophical Investigations, op. cit., No. 258.
22 Wall, P. D., op. cit., 301.Google Scholar
23 Philosophical Investigations, op. cit., No. 281.
24 Hamlyn, D. W., ‘Behaviour’, Philosophy, 27 (1953).Google Scholar
25 I have discussed the theory of action underlying these remarks in ‘Actions, Causes and Mental Ascriptions’, in Objections to Physicalism, Robinson, H. (ed.) (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990).Google Scholar
26 ‘Representations and Cognitive Science’, Inquiry 32 (1989), 261–277.Google Scholar
27 I have used ‘information’ in an undefined way here but there are important distinctions to be made when one is looking at the nature of representation in epistemology and cognitive science. On this see op. cit. note 25.
28 ‘Perception and Neuroscience’ British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 40 (1989) 83–103.Google Scholar Also, Churchland, P., Neurophilosophy (Cambridge (Mass.): M.I.T. Press, 1986).Google Scholar
29 Philosophical Investigations, op. cit., No. 580.
- 6
- Cited by