Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-18T01:26:25.606Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Love's Constancy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 January 2009

Mike W. Martin
Affiliation:
Chapman University

Extract

‘Marital faithfulness’ refers to faithful love for a spouse or lover to whom one is committed, rather than the narrower idea of sexual fidelity. The distinction is clearly marked in traditional wedding vows. A commitment to love faithfully is central: ‘to have and to hold from this day forward, for better for worse, for richer for poorer, in sickness and in health, to love and to cherish, till death us do part… and thereto I plight [pledge] thee my troth [faithfulness]’. Sexual fidelity is promised in a subordinate clause, symbolizing its supportive role in promoting love's constancy: ‘and, forsaking all other, keep thee only unto her/him.’

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1993

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Church of England Prayer Book (1549). I will understand marriage as a moral relationship centred on lifelong commitments to love and significantly involving sexual desire at some time during the relationship, whether or not the marriage is formalized in legal or religious ceremonies, recognizing homo sexual as well as heterosexual marriages, and independently of government intrusions. On the latter see Palmer, David, ‘The Consolation of the Wedded’, in Philosophy and Sex, 2nd edn, Baker, Robert and Elliston, Frederick (eds) (Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books, 1984), 119129.Google Scholar

2 Or its presumed supportive role. Some couples, of course, enter into (or transform their relationship into) ‘open marriages’ in which they permit extramarital affairs while retaining lifetime commitments. For an early and especially interesting example, see Nicolson's, Nigel portrayal of his parents in Portrait of a Marriage (New York: Atheneum, 1973)Google Scholar. Two illuminating (and contrasting) discussions of the rationale for traditional links between lifetime marital commitments and sexual fidelity are: Leites, Edmund, The Puritan Conscience and Modern Sexuality (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1986)Google Scholar, and Scruton, Roger, Sexual Desire (New York: Free Press, 1986).Google Scholar

3 Singer, Irving develops the idea of love as a special way of valuing persons in his masterful three-volume study, The Nature of Love (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984, 1987)Google Scholar. Whereas I understand (‘true’) love as permeated by the virtues, Singer separates morality and love, as a result of his constricted view of morality as demanding impartiality (by contrast with love's preference for one individual). See especially p. 11 of vol. I.

4 Tolstoy, Leo, Great Short Works of Leo Tolstoy, trans. Louise, and Maude, Aylmer (New York: Harper and Row, 1967), 361362Google Scholar. Also see Gilbert's, Paul discussion in Human Relationships (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991), 9ff.Google Scholar

5 Wilson, John, ‘Can One Promise to Love Another?Philosophy 64 (1989), 560CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Also see Sankowski, Edward, ‘Responsibility of Persons for Their Emotions’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 12 (1977), 829840.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

6 Oksenberg Rorty, Amélie argues that the core of some emotions is a pattern of attention rather than the more common beliefs and attitudes in ‘Explaining Emotions’, in Explaining Emotions (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980), 103126.Google Scholar

7 Cf. Seligman, Martin E. P., Learned Optimism (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1991).Google Scholar

8 Hunter, J. F. M., Thinking about Sex and Love (Toronto: Macmillan of Canada, 1980), 59.Google Scholar

9 Except when it inspires individuals to do more than they could have otherwise. On this, and on the entire topic of ‘ought implies can’, see Resche, Nicholasr, Ethical Idealism (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1987).Google Scholar

10 Cf. Hatchings, P. E., ‘Conjugal Faithfulness’, Human Values, Vesey, Godfrey (ed.) (New Jersey: Humanities Press, 1978).Google Scholar

11 Hunter, J. F. M., Thinking about Sex and Love, 59Google Scholar. Cf. Parfit, Derek, ‘Later Selves and Moral Principles’, Philosophy and Personal Relations, Montefiore, A. (ed.) (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1973).Google Scholar

12 Mendus, Susan, ‘Marital Faithfulness’, Philosophy 59 (1984), 246.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

13 P. 247.

14 Soble, Alan, The Structure of Love (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1990), 166167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

15 Solomon, Robert, Love: Emotion, Myth and Metaphor (Garden City, NY: Anchor Press, 1981), 224.Google Scholar

16 P. 227.

17 Cf. Blum, Lawrence A., Friendship, Altruism and Morality (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1980).Google Scholar

18 Solomon, Robert, About Love (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1988), 40.Google Scholar

19 P. 134.

20 Midgley, Mary, Beast and Man (New York: New American Library, 1980), 303.Google Scholar

21 Slote, Michael, Goods and Virtues (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), 62ff.Google Scholar

22 Nussbaum, Martha C., The Fragility of Goodness (Cambridge University Press, 1986), 359361.Google Scholar

23 Williams, Bernard, Moral Luck (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1981), 26ff.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

24 Russell, Bertrand, The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell, Vol. 1 (New York: Bantam Books, 1968), 195196.Google Scholar

25 Quoted by Strachey, Barbara in Remarkable Relations (London: Victor Gollancz, 1980), 216.Google Scholar

26 Midgley, Mary, Wisdom, Information and Wonder (New York: Routledge, 1989), p. 157.Google Scholar

27 Nin, Anaïs, Henry and June (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1986), 29.Google Scholar

28 P. 229.

29 Slote, Michael, Goods and Virtues, 77ff.Google Scholar

30 Sonnet, 116.Google Scholar

31 Day, Dorothy, The Long Loneliness (New York: Harper & Row, 1952), 147148.Google Scholar

32 Nietzsche, Friedrich, The Gay Science, trans. Kaufmann, Walter (New York: Vintage Books, 1974), 232.Google Scholar