Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-g7gxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T09:30:07.335Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Idea of Cause1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 February 2009

Extract

Some modern thinkers have supposed that “cause” is an outworn notion, or at least that it is one of which modern science has no need. This is due mainly to the discovery that, while the scientist can give us general laws as to what in fact happens, he cannot help us to discern the reason for the laws or the inward nature of the forces on which they depend. He can tell us the “that” but not the “why”; he cannot show us in a single case that the effect follows necessarily a priori from the nature of the cause, that any other effect than the one which actually takes place would be logically impossible. He has studied the law of gravitation, but this law does not enable him to see why material bodies should attract each other in this fashion; it is only a generalized statement of the fact that they do. He knows that certain substances, if absorbed by eating, will nourish and others destroy our tissues; but he cannot say why they should do so. He can no doubt analyse them further and discover that, for example, meat is nourishing because it contains a large proportion of nitrogenous matter, but he could not tell a priori whether this nitrogenous matter would be likely to nourish or to poison us. Only where mathematics can be applied do we see necessity in such a way that any alternative becomes inconceivable to us; but mathematics alone can never establish from a quantity present here and now what quantity there will be at a later time or in another part of space. Mathematics can show, e.g., that, if there is 2 + 2 here and now, there must be 4 here and now, not that, if there is 2 + 2 here and now, there will be 4 in an hour's time or a mile away; and therefore it cannot be made the sole basis of any causal law whatever.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1929

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 456 note 1 I mean here by subjective idealism the view that we must not assume the existence of objects in space except as human perceptions, the reality which causes these perceptions being held to be either mental or totally unknowable, so that all our propositions about physical objects have sense only if they are interpreted as being merely statements about our perceptions. In that case Kant's argument, as it stands, proves causality, in the sense of necessary determination, for physical objects, since it proves it for perceptions, and physical objects (i.e. objects in space) are in that case only our perceptions or systems of our perceptions. But it does not prove it for the “realist,” since the latter holds that physical objects exist quite independently of our perceiving them.

page 457 note 1 This is not intended to prejudge the question whether the physical world, though independent of our minds as finite, is ultimately dependent on Mind, and is not therefore inconsistent with many forms of “idealism.” Nor is it meant that physical objects are very like what we in our unsophisticated moments take them to be.

page 462 note 1 I do not mean by “mechanical causality’ only causality explicable by the laws of motion, but am referring to any view which anticipates the explanation of everything by causal laws in, the sense expressed in this paragraph, whether it relies entirely on physical or also admits, in human life, psychological causes.