Article contents
Freedom1
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 25 February 2009
Extract
In this paper I intend to do two things. The first is to discuss a method of doing philosophy, the method of ‘ordinary language’ philosophy, as it is commonly and misleadingly called. (Its other common title: ‘Oxford Philosophy’ is even more misleading, since the roots of the method lie in Cambridge, and many of the most flourishing branches are in the United States rather than England.)If it needs a name, perhaps the best is—adapting Popper to our purpose—‘piecemeal philosophical engineering’. Such a title would emphasise the attention to detail and the caution about conclusions that characterise the best of such work. The second aim of this paper is to apply the method thus discussed and defended to three questions connected with the concept of freedom. These problems arise out of three recent discussions of freedom—Thought and Action and Spinoza and the Idea of Freedom by Professor Hampshire, and Two Concepts of Liberty by Professor Berlin.
- Type
- Articles
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1965
References
page 94 note 1 Most of this section is highly derivative: sources of particular importance are Ryle: ‘Ordinary Language’ in Philosophical Review 1953, Cavell: ‘Must we Mean what we Say?’ Inquiry, 1958.Google Scholar
page 99 note 1 Reviewing Austin: Sense and Sensibilia in Oxford Magazine, 12 1962.Google Scholar
page 106 note 1 This is unfair to Flew's later views; but perhaps not to the view expressed in New Essays in Philosophical Theology.Google Scholar
- 3
- Cited by