Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-94fs2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-18T03:18:16.521Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Fellow-Feeling Paradox: Hume, Smith and the Moral Order*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 July 2015

Abstract

Hume and Smith advance different answers to the question of whether sympathy can ever be the foundation of the moral order. They hold contradictory views of sympathy, called here ‘the Fellow-Feeling Paradox’. For Hume, fellow-feeling tends to reverberate in society, leading to the socialization of the individual and even mob (collective) psychology. Hence, sympathy cannot be the foundation of the moral order. In contrast, for Smith, fellow-feeling develops into critical judgment of the emotions/actions, leading to individual moral autonomy even self-command. Hence, sympathy can be the foundation of the moral order. This paper provides a resolution of the two answers.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 2015 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

The paper was supported by the Konrad Lorenz Institute for Evolution and Cognition Research and Monash University's Faculty Research Grant. An earlier version received comments from Philippe Fontaine, Ulrich Krohs, Robert Sugden, Aldo Rustichini, Ian McDonald, Caroline Gerschlager, Herbert Gintis, Robin Pope, Taiki Takahashi, Roland Cheo Kim San, Jonathan Wight, Steven Gardner, and many seminar participants. The usual caveat applies.

References

1 Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L., Gallese, V., and Fogassi, L., ‘Premotor Cortex and the Recognition of Motor Actions’, Cognitive Brain Research 3 (1996), 131141 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

2 Gallese, V., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., and Rizzolatti, G., ‘Action Recognition in the Premotor Cortex’, Brain 119 (1996), 593609 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

3 Khalil, E.L., ‘The Mirror-Neuron Paradox: How Far is Understanding from Mimicking?Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 77 (2011), 8696 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4 Khalil, E.L., ‘Deciphering Mirror Neurons: Rational-Decision vs. Associative-Learning’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 37 (2014), 206207 Google Scholar.

5 J. Cropsey, Polity and Economy: An Interpretation of the Principles of Adam Smith (South Bend, IN: St. Augustine's Press, 2001).

6 Raynor, D., ‘Adam Smith and the Virtues’. Adam Smith Review 2 (2006), 239245 Google Scholar, Vivien Brown (ed.).

7 Gordon, R.M., ‘Sympathy, Simulation and the Impartial Spectator’, Ethics 105 (1995), 727742 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 Darwall, S., ‘Empathy, Sympathy, Care’, Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition89 (1998), 261282 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

9 C.L. Griswold, Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999).

10 Nanay, ‘B., ‘Adam Smith's Concept of Sympathy and its Contemporary Interpretations’, Adam Smith Review 5 (2010), 85105 Google Scholar, V. Brown and S. Fleischacker (eds).

11 V. Brown, ‘Intersubjectivity and Moral Judgment in Adam Smith's Theory of Moral Sentiments’, in Christel Fricke and Dagfinn Føllesdal (eds) Intersubjectivity and Objectivity in Adam Smith and Edmund Husserl: A Collection of Essays (Frankfurt: Ontos-Verlag, 2012, 243–271).

12 Carrasco, M.A., ‘Adam Smith: Self-Command, Practical Reason and Deontological Insights’, British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (2012), 391414 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13 S. Fleischacker, ‘Sympathy in Hume and Smith: A Contrast, Critique and Reconstruction’, in Christel Fricke and Dagfinn Føllesdal (eds) Intersubjectivity and Objectivity in Adam Smith and Edmund Husserl: A Collection of Essays (Frankfurt: Ontos-Verlag, 2012, 273–311).

14 A. Smith, The Theory of Moral Sentiments (eds) D.D. Raphael and A.L. Macfie (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1976).

15 A.S. Skinner, A System of Social Science: Papers Relating to Adam Smith (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979, ch. 3).

16 A.L. Macfie, The Individual in Society: Papers on Adam Smith (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1967, 75).

17 A.S. Skinner, ‘Introduction’, in Adam Smith's The Wealth of Nations (Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin, 1971, 21).

18 Khalil, E.L., ‘Beyond Self-Interest and Altruism: A Reconstruction of Adam Smith's Theory of Human Conduct’, Economics and Philosophy 6 (1990), 255273 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19 Gallese, V. and Goldman, A., ‘Mirror Neurons and the Simulation Theory of Mind-Reading’, Trends in Cognitive Sciences 2 (1998), 493501 Google ScholarPubMed.

20 A.I. Goldman, Simulating Minds: The Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience of Mindreading (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2006).

21 M. Davies, ‘The Mental Simulation Debate’, in C. Peacocke (ed.) Objectivity, Simulation and the Unity of Consciousness: Current Issues in the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994, 99–127).

22 T. Stone and M. Davies, ‘The Mental Dimulation Debate: A Progress Report’, in P. Carruthers and P.K. Smith (eds), Theories of Theories of Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996, 119–37).

23 Op. cit. note 7, 727–742.

24 Op. cit. note 8, 261–282.

25 Op. cit. note 10, 85–105.

26 Op. cit. note 21, 99–127.

27 Op. cit. note 11, 243–271.

28 Op. cit. note 9.

29 Op. cit. note 3, 86–96.

30 Op. cit. note 10, 85–105.

31 Op. cit. note 13, 273–311.

32 B. Mandeville, The Fable of the Bees, or, Private Vices, Publick Benefits (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Classics, (1714) 1988).

33 A.O. Hirschman, The Passions and the Interests: Political Arguments for Capitalism before its Triumph (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1977).

34 Op. cit. note 13, 273–311.

35 R. Crisp, ‘Hume on Virtue, Utility, and Morality’, in S.M. Gardiner (ed.) Virtue Ethics, Old and New (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2005, 159–178).

36 D. Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, 3 vols, edited by L.A. Selby-Bigge (Oxford: Clarendon Press, (1740) 1896, 577–580).

37 Sobel, J.H., ‘Hume's Utilitarian Theory of Right Action’, Philosophical Quarterly (1997) 5572 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

38 Op. cit. note 35.

39 Op. cit. note 36, 365.

40 Op. cit. note 36, vol. III.2, 486.

41 Still, the suppression of the expression of pain, such as the pain of hunger, may help the person to feel less hungry. By training the mind to focus less on pain, the agent may break the biological cycle: to think less of food and hunger may help the person to attenuate the original pain of hunger. For Sigmund Freud, the contrary is the case: Suppression of original emotions, especially emotions related to the sexual desire, would ignite further, rather than attenuate, the original emotions.

42 These scholars of Smith also discuss the letter: Op. cit. note 13; Levy, D.M. and Peart, S.J., ‘Sympathy and Approbation in Hume and Smith: A Solution to the Other Rational Species Problem’, Economics and Philosophy 20 (2004), 331349 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Sugden, R., ‘Beyond Sympathy and Empathy: Adam Smith's Concept of Fellow-Feeling’, Economics and Philosophy 18 (2002), 6387 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

43 A. Smith, The Correspondence of Adam Smith, (ed.) E.C. Mossner and I.S. Moss (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977, 43).

44 Op. cit. note 43, 43.

45 A.T. Siraki ‘Adam Smith's Solution to the Paradox of Tragedy’. Adam Smith Review 5 (2010), 213–230, V. Brown and S. Fleischacker (eds).

46 Khalil, E.L., ‘Adam Smith's Concept of Self-Command as a Solution to Dynamic Inconsistency and the Commitment Problem’, Economic Inquiry 48 (2010), 177191 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

47 As mentioned earlier, Smith's conflation of understanding (empathy) with approval (sympathy in Smith's sense) is problematic – if not a major weakness of Smith's theory.

48 Op. cit. note 46.

49 Op. cit. note 12.

50 Op. cit. note 14,156–161.

51 Khalil, E.L., ‘Self-Deceit and Self-Serving Bias: Adam Smith on “General Rules”’, Journal of Institutional Economics 5 (2009), 251258 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

52 Op. cit. note 14, 14.

53 Fleischacker (Op. cit. note 13, 301–302) employs almost the same terminology, ‘first-order feeling’ and ‘second-order feeling’, to denote Smith's distinction. While Brown (Op. cit. note 11, 247) notes the distinction, and calls the second-order sympathy ‘sentiment of approbation’, she treats it as a ‘further emotion’, i.e., it does not form an essential part in her understanding of Smith's technical notion of sympathy.

54 Op. cit. note 14, 209.

55 Op. cit. note 14, 46n.

56 Op. cit. note 45, 213–230.

57 Op. cit. note 14, 10–11, n.1.

58 Op. cit. note 14, 10.

59 Op. cit. note 14, 10.

60 Op. cit. note 14, 11.

61 Op. cit. note 14, 11–12.

62 Op. cit. note 13, 281–282.

63 Op. cit. note 14, 12.

64 F. Nietzsche, ‘The Anti-Christ: Curse on Christianity’, in K.A. Pearson D. Large (eds) The Nietzsche Reader (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2006, 488).

65 Op. cit. note 14, 120.

66 Op. cit. note 14, 156.

67 This should not mean that Hume cannot explain attenuation. He can, but only in particular cases and for accidental reasons. That is, he cannot systematically explain attenuation in the sense that he cannot relate to his theory of sympathy.

68 Op. cit. note 14, 52.

69 Khalil, E.L., ‘Is Adam Smith Liberal?Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 158 (2002), 664694 Google Scholar.

70 Khalil, E.L., ‘An Anatomy of Authority: Adam Smith as Political Theorist’, Cambridge Journal of Economics 29 (2005), 5771 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

71 Op. cit. note 14, 50–66.

72 Khalil, E.L., ‘Is Justice the Primary Feature of the State? Adam Smith's Critique of Social Contract Theory’, European Journal of Law and Economics 6 (1998), 215230 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.