Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-vsgnj Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-22T04:34:20.288Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

William James’s Objection to Epiphenomenalism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

James developed an evolutionary objection to epiphenomenalism that is still discussed today. Epiphenomenalists have offered responses that do not grasp its full depth. I thus offer a new reading and assessment of James’s objection. Our life-essential, phenomenal pleasures and pains have three features that suggest that they were shaped by selection, according to James: they are natively patterned, those patterns are systematically linked with antecedent brain states, and the patterns are “universal” among humans. If epiphenomenalism were true, phenomenal patterns could not have been selected (because epiphenomenalism precludes phenomenal consciousness affecting reproductive success). So epiphenomenalism is likely false.

Type
Cognitive Sciences
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I would like to thank Trevor Pearce and Elisabeth Lloyd for helpful feedback, as well as the US-UK Fulbright Commission, which financially supported this work.

References

Allen, Grant. 1877. Physiological Aesthetics. New York: Appleton.Google Scholar
Andrews, P. W., Gangestad, S. W., and Matthews, D.. 2002. “Adaptationism: How to Carry out an Exaptationist Program.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25 (4): 489504..CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Corabi, Joseph. 2008. “Pleasure’s Role in Evolution: A Response to Robinson.” Journal of Consciousness Studies 15 (7): 7886..Google Scholar
Corabi, Joseph. 2014. “The Misuse and Failure of the Evolutionary Argument.” Disputatio: International Journal of Philosophy 6 (39): 199227..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flanagan, Owen J. 1992. Consciousness Reconsidered. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Futuyma, Douglas J. 2005. Evolution. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.Google Scholar
Gould, Stephen Jay, and Lewontin, Richard C.. 1979. “The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme.” Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B 205 (1161): 581–98..Google Scholar
Hazen, Robert M., Griffin, Patrick L., Carothers, James M., and Szostak, Jack W.. 2007. “Functional Information and the Emergence of Biocomplexity.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 104 (Suppl. 1): 8574–81.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hodgson, Shadworth Hollway. 1865. Time and Space: A Metaphysical Essay. London: Longman, Green, Longman, Roberts, & Green.Google Scholar
Huxley, Thomas Henry. 1874/1894. “On the Hypothesis That Animals Are Automata, and Its History.” In Collected Essays: Method and Results, 199250. New York: Appleton.Google Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 1982. “Epiphenomenal Qualia.” Philosophical Quarterly 32 (127): 127–36..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
James, William. 1879. “Are We Automata?Mind 4 (13): 122..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
James, William. 1890/1981. The Principles of Psychology. In The Works of William James, ed. Burkhardt, Frederick H., Bowers, Fredson, and Skrupskelis, Ignas K.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Klein, Alexander. 2018. “The Curious Case of the Decapitated Frog: On Experiment and Philosophy.” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 26 (5): 890917..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Klein, Alexander. Forthcoming. “The Death of Consciousness? James’s Case against Psychological Unobservables.” Journal of the History of Philosophy.Google Scholar
Lloyd, Elisabeth A., and Gould, Stephen Jay. 2017. “Exaptation Revisited: Changes Imposed by Evolutionary Psychologists and Behavioral Biologists.” Biological Theory 12 (1): 5065..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, Shaun, and Grantham, Todd. 2000. “Adaptive Complexity and Phenomenal Consciousness.” Philosophy of Science 67 (4): 648–70..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pearce, Trevor. 2018. “James and Evolution.” In The Oxford Handbook of William James, ed. Klein, Alexander. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R., and Eccles, John C.. 1977. The Self and Its Brain: An Argument for Interactionism. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richards, Robert J. 1987. Darwin and the Emergence of Evolutionary Theories of Mind and Behavior. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, William S. 2004. Understanding Phenomenal Consciousness. Cambridge Studies in Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, William S.. 2007. “Evolution and Epiphenomenalism.” Journal of Consciousness Studies 14 (11): 2742..Google Scholar
Robinson, William S.. 2014. “James’s Evolutionary Argument.” Disputatio: International Journal of Philosophy 6 (39): 229–37..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, William S.. 2015. “Epiphenomenalism.” In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Zalta, Edward N.. Stanford, CA: Stanford University. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2015/entries/epiphenomenalism/.Google Scholar
Robinson, Zack, Maley, Corey J., and Piccinini, Gualtiero. 2015. “Is Consciousness a Spandrel?Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1 (2): 365–83..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Symons, Donald. 1990. “Adaptiveness and Adaptation.” Ethology and Sociobiology 11 (4): 427–44..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wiener, Philip P. 1949. Evolution and the Founders of Pragmatism. New York: Harper Torchbooks.Google Scholar
Williams, George C. 1966. Adaptation and Natural Selection: A Critique of Some Current Evolutionary Thought. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Wright, John. 2015. “On James’s Argument against Epiphenomenalism.” William James Studies 11:6985.Google Scholar