Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-r5fsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T04:07:14.016Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Towards an Empirically Adequate Theory of Science

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Janet A. Kourany*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Notre Dame

Abstract

While there has been general agreement among modern philosophers of science that a purely a priori method is inappropriate to the task of establishing a theory of science, there has, unfortunately, been little comparable agreement regarding the method that is appropriate. I try to lay the foundations for such agreement. I first set out reasons for a purely empirical method for establishing a theory of science, and defend such a method against charges raised by Giere. I then develop some very basic criteria for the evaluation of alternative empirical methods for establishing a theory of science, and use these criteria to evaluate the two such methods that have dominated philosophic discussion in recent years—those of Lakatos and Laudan. I end by defending a revised version of Lakatos’ proposal.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1982

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I wish to thank Larry Laudan, Ernan McMullin, Thomas Kuhn, and an anonymous referee of this journal for very helpful comments on earlier versions of the present paper. I wish, also, to thank the University of Utah Research Committee for its very generous assistance in the form of a David P. Gardner Faculty Fellowship and a Faculty Research Grant. Versions of this paper were presented at the University of Notre Dame, 1980, and at the Sixth Regional Conference on the History and Philosophy of Science, University of Colorado, Boulder, 1982.

References

Achinstein, P. (1977), “History and Philosophy of Science: A Reply to Cohen”, in F. Suppe (ed.) (1977c): 350360.Google Scholar
Asquith, P. and Giere, R. (eds.) (1980), PSA 1980 1. East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
Asquith, P. and Kyburg, H. (eds.) (1979), Current Research in Philosophy of Science. East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
Beckman, T. A. (1971), “On the Use of Historical Examples in Agassi's ‘Sensationalism'”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 1: 293309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, J. (1980), “History and the Norms of Science”, in P. Asquith and R. Giere (eds.) (1980): 236248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buck, R. C. and Cohen, R. S. (eds.) (1971), PSA 1970. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 8. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Burian, R. (1977), “More Than a Marriage of Convenience: On the Inextricability of History and Philosophy of Science”, Philosophy of Science 44: 142.10.1086/288722CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K. (1976), “On the Critique of Scientific Reason”, in C. Howson (ed.) (1976): 309339.Google Scholar
Giere, R. (1973), “History and Philosophy of Science: Intimate Relationship or Marriage of Convenience?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 24: 282297.10.1093/bjps/24.3.282CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giere, R. (1975), “The Epistemological Roots of Scientific Knowledge”, in Maxwell, G. and Anderson, R. (eds.), Induction, Probability, and Confirmation. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 6. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press: 212261.Google Scholar
Gutting, G. (1980), “Progress and Its Problems: A Review”, Erkenntnis 15: 91103.Google Scholar
Hall, R. (1971), “Can We Use the History of Science to Decide Between Competing Methodologies?” in R. C. Buck and R. S. Cohen (eds.): 151159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heidelberger, M. (1976), “Some Intertheoretic Relations between Ptolemean and Copernican Astronomy”, Erkenntnis 10: 323336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howson, C. (ed.) (1976), Method and Appraisal in the Physical Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511760013CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joergensen, J. (1951), The Development of Logical Empiricism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Koertge, N. (1976), “Rational Reconstructions”, in Cohen, R. S., Feyerabend, P. K., and Wartofsky, M. W. (eds.), Essays in Memory of Imre Lakatos. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 39. Dordrecht: D. Reidel: 359369.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kourany, J. (1979), “The Nonhistorical Basis of Kuhn's Theory of Science”, Nature and System 1: 4659.Google Scholar
Kourany, J. (Forthcoming), “Review of The Rationality of Science by W. H. Newton-Smith”, The Journal of Philosophy.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. (1971), “Notes on Lakatos”, in R. C. Buck and R. S. Cohen (eds.) (1971): 137146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kulka, T. (1977), “Some Problems Concerning Rational Reconstruction: Comments on Elkana and Lakatos”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 28: 325344.10.1093/bjps/28.4.325CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, I. (1970), “Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programs”, in I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave (eds.). Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge: Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 91195.10.1017/CBO9781139171434.009CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, I. (1976), “History of Science and Its Rational Reconstructions”, in C. Howson (ed.) (1976): 139.10.1017/CBO9780511760013.002CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, I. (1978), “Popper on Demarcation and Induction”, in Worrall, J. and Currie, G. (eds.), Imre Lakatos: The Methodology of Scientific Research Programs. Philosophical Papers 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 139167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. (1977), Progress and Its Problems. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1979), “Historical Methodologies: An Overview and Manifesto”, in P. Asquith and H. Kyburg (eds.): 4054.Google Scholar
Laymon, R. (1977), “Feyerabend, Brownian Motion, and the Hiddenness of Refuting Facts”, Philosophy of Science 44: 225247.10.1086/288740CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Losee, J. (1978), “Laudan on Progress in Science”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 9: 333340.10.1016/0039-3681(78)90014-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machamer, P. (1973), “Feyerabend and Galileo”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 4: 146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mandelbaum, M. (1977), “A Note on Thomas S. Kuhn's The Structure of Scientific Revolutions“, Historicism and Epistemology, The Monist 60: 445452.Google Scholar
McEvoy, J. (1975), “A ‘Revolutionary’ Philosophy of Science: Feyerabend and the Degeneration of Critical Rationalism into Skeptical Fallibilism”, Philosophy of Science 42: 4966.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMullin, E. (1970), “The History and Philosophy of Science: A Taxonomy”, in Stuewer, R. (ed.), Historical and Philosophical Perspectives of Science. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 5. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press: 1267.Google Scholar
McMullin, E. (1975), “History and Philosophy of Science: A Marriage of Convenience?” in Cohen, R. S. and Michalos, A. C. (eds.), PSA 1974. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 32. Dordrecht: D. Reidel: 515531.Google Scholar
Newton-Smith, W. H. (1981), The Rationality of Science. Boston: Routledge and Kegan Paul.10.4324/9780203317211CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. (1959), The Logic of Scientific Discovery. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Ruse, M. (1970), “The Revolution in Biology”, Theoria 36: 122.10.1111/j.1755-2567.1970.tb00407.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruse, M. (1971), “Two Biological Revolutions”, Dialectica 25: 1738.10.1111/j.1746-8361.1971.tb00590.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapere, D. (1964), “The Structure of Scientific Revolutions”, The Philosophical Review 73: 383394.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapere, D. (1966), “Meaning and Scientific Change”, in Colodny, R. (ed.), Mind and Cosmos. Pittsburgh Series in the Philosophy of Science 3. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press: 4185.Google Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. (1972), “Science, History and Methodology”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 23: 266274.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suppe, F. (1977a), “The Search for Philosophic Understanding of Scientific Theories”, in F. Suppe (ed.) (1977c): 3241.Google Scholar
Suppe, F. (1977b), “Afterword—1977”, in F. Suppe (ed.), (1977c): 617730.Google Scholar
Suppe, F. (ed.) (1977c), The Structure of Scientific Theories, 2nd ed. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
Williams, L. P. (1975), “Should Philosophers Be Allowed to Write History?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 26: 241253.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Worrall, J. (1976), “Thomas Young and the ‘Refutation’ of Newtonian Optics: A Case-Study in the Interaction of Philosophy of Science and History”, in C. Howson (ed.) (1976): 107179.10.1017/CBO9780511760013.004CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wykstra, S. (1978), The Interdependence of History of Science and Philosophy of Science: Toward a Meta-Theory of Scientific Rationality. Unpublished Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Pittsburgh.Google Scholar
Wykstra, S. (1980), “Toward a Historical Meta-Method for Assessing Normative Methodologies: Rationability, Serendipity, and the Robinson Crusoe Fallacy”, in P. Asquith and R. Giere (eds.) (1980): 211222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar