Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t8hqh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T04:05:38.657Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Structure of a Scientific Paper

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Frederick Suppe*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Committee on the History and Philosophy of Science, University of Maryland

Abstract

Scientific articles exemplify standard functional units constraining argumentative structures. Severe space limitations demand every paragraph and illustration contribute to establishing the paper's claims. Philosophical testing and confirmation models should take into account each paragraph, table, and illustration. Hypothetico-Deductive, Bayesian Inductive, and Inference-to-the-Best-Explanation models do not, garbling the logic of papers. Micro-analysis of the fundamental paper in plate tectonics reveals an argumentative structure commonplace in science but ignored by standard philosophical accounts that cannot be dismissed as mere rhetorical embellishment. Papers with illustrations often display a second argumentative structure differing from the text's. Constraints on adequate testing and confirmation analyses are adduced.

“Experiments are about the assembly of persuasive arguments, ones that will stand up in court. … The task at hand is to capture the building-up of a persuasive argument about the world even in the absence of the logician's certainty.”

—Galison, How Experiments End, 277.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1998

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Send reprint requests to the author, Philosophy/CHPS, 1102 Skinner, University of Maryland, College Park, MD 20742.

Drafts were presented at the Princeton Geological & Geophysical Sciences Junior Colloquium, University of South Carolina, The College of Charleston/Medical College of South Carolina Humanities Colloquium, Indiana University, University of Illinois/Urbana, and Northwestern University. I am grateful to John Suppe, Bas van Fraassen, Arthur Fine, Alfred Noordmann, Don E. Dulany, Christopher P. Stone, colleagues in the Princeton Department of Geological and Geophysical Sciences, and students in my University of Maryland Fall 1994 “Seminar on Models in Science” for comments or other help; Ken Deffeyes for goading me into doing the Morgan 1968 microanalysis; and Jason Morgan for access to archival materials and several oral history opportunities concerning his 1968 paper and its 1967 AGU predecessor. Support was provided by: University of Maryland General Research Board, National Science Foundation, University of Maryland Prestigious Fellowships Program, Princeton Department of Geological and Geophysical Sciences, and the Indiana University Institute for Advanced Study.

References

Achinstein, P. (1991), Particles and Waves: Historical Essays in the Philosophy of Science. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bastide, F. (1990), “The Iconography of Scientific Texts: Principles of Analysis”, in Lynch, M. and Woolgar, S. (eds.), Representation in Scientific Practice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 187230.Google Scholar
Box, G. (1980), “Sampling and Bayes' Inference in Scientific Modelling and Robustness”, Journal of the Royal Statistical Society 243/4: 383404.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Box, G. (1983), “An Apology for Ecumenism in Statistics”, in Box, Leonard, and Wu (eds.) 1983, pp. 5184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Box, G., Leonard, T., and Wu, C. (1983), Scientific Inference, Data Analysis, and Robustness. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Bullard, Sir E., Everett, J., and Smith, A. (1965), “The Fit of the Continents Around the Atlantic”, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, Series A, 258: 141151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burks, A. (1977), Chance, Cause, Reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Collins, H. (1975), “The Seven Sexes: A Study in the Sociology of a Phenomenon, or the Replication of Experiments in Physics”, Sociology 9: 205224.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, H. (1985), Changing Order: Replication and Induction in Scientific Practice. Beverly Hills: Sage.Google Scholar
Cox, A. and Hart, R. (1986), Plate Tectonics: How it Works. Boston: Blackwell Scientific Publications.Google Scholar
Galison, P. (1987), How Experiments End. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Garvey, W. and Griffith, B. (1971), “Scientific Communication: Its Role in the Conduct of Research and Creation of Knowledge”, American Psychologist 26: 349362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, G. (1976), “The Transformation of Research Findings to Scientific Knowledge”, Social Studies of Science 6: 281306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, G. and Mulkay, M. (1984), Opening Pandora's Box: A Sociological Analysis of Scientists' Discourse. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gubbins, D. (1990), Seismology and Plate Tectonics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Harman, G. (1965), “The Inference to the Best Explanation”, Philosophical Review 74:88–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. (1968), “Knowledge, Inference and Explanation”, American Philosophical Quarterly 5: 164173.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. (1965), Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in Philosophy of Science. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. (1966), Philosophy of Natural Science. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Holton, G. (1973), Thematic Origins of Scientific Thought: Kepler to Einstein. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Horwich, P. (1982), Probability and Evidence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Howson, C. and Urbach, P. (1989), Scientific Reasoning: The Bayesian Approach. La Salle: Open Court.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1991), “Persuasion”, in Pera and Shea 1991, pp. 328.Google Scholar
Le Pichon, X. (1968), “Sea-floor Spreading and Continental Drift”, Journal of Geophysical Research 73: 36613697.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Le Pichon, X. (1977), “A Personal and probably Biased View of Plate Tectonics Hypothesis Formulation and Evolution” (abstract), EOS 58/6: 367.Google Scholar
Le Pichon, X. (1991), “Introduction to the publication of the extended outline of Jason Morgan's April 17, 1967 American Geophysical Union paper on ‘Rises, Trenches, Great Faults, and Crustal Blocks’ ”, Tectonophysics 187/1–3: 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lindley, D. (1965), Introduction to Probability and Statistics From a Bayesian Viewpoint, Volume I: Probability. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lowe, E. (1980), “Sortal Terms and Natural Laws: An Essay on the Ontological Status of Laws of Nature”, American Philosophical Quarterly 17: 253260.Google Scholar
Lynch, M. (1985), Art and Artifact in Laboratory Science: A Study of Shop Work and Shop Talk in a Research Laboratory. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Medawar, P. (1963), “Is the Scientific Paper a Fraud?”, The Listener & BBC Television Review 70, no. 1798, Thursday, Sept. 12, 1963, 377378.Google Scholar
Menard, H. (1967), “Extension of Northeastern-Pacific Fracture ZonesScience 155: 7274.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Menard, H. (1986), Ocean of Truth: A Personal History of Global Tectonics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morgan, W. J. (1967), “Rises, Trenches, Great Faults, and Crustal Blocks”, manuscript presented April 17, 1967 in a symposium, “Sea Floor Spreading”, American Geophysical Union Meeting, Washington. D.C.; manuscript later published in photo-reproduction form as pp. 6–22 of Le Pichon 1991.Google Scholar
Morgan, W. J. (1968), “Rises, Trenches, Great Faults, and Crustal Blocks”, Journal of Geophysical Research 73/6 (March 15): 19591982.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mulkay, M. (1984), “The Scientist Talks Back: A One-Act Play, with a Moral about Replication in Science and Reflexivity in Sociology”, Social Studies of Science 14: 265282.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mulkay, M. (1985), The Word and the World: Explorations in the Form of Sociological Analysis. London: George Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
Mulkay, M. and Gilbert, G. (1986), “Replication and Mere Replication”, Philosophy of Social Science 16: 2137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pera, M. and Shea, W. (1991), Persuading Science: The Art of Scientific Rhetoric. Canton, MA: Science History Publications.Google Scholar
Salmon, W. (1967), Foundations of Scientific Inference. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Savage, L. J. (1954), Foundations of Statistics. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Suppe, F. (1989), The Semantic Conception of Theories and Scientific Realism. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
Suppe, F. (1993), “Credentialing Scientific Claims”, Perspectives on Science 1/2: 153203.Google Scholar
Suppe, F. (1997), “Science Without Induction”, in Earman, John and Norton, John (eds.), The Cosmos of Science. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press and Konstanz: Universitätsverlag Konstanz, 1997, pp. 386429.Google Scholar
Suppe, F. (1999), Facts, Theories, and Scientific Observation, Volume 1: A Posteriori Knowledge and Truth, Volume 2: Scientific Knowledge. Forthcoming (under review).Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1980), The Scientific Image. New York: Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1989), Laws and Symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar