1. Introduction
Microaggressions are relatively minor slights and offenses that can appear individually innocuous, but that in aggregate may explain significant gaps in health and other domains. The microaggression concept has been the object of vigorous attention in public discussions, DEI (diversity, equity, and inclusion) work, and in research in psychology, public health, philosophy, and other fields. The term “microaggression” now serves a multiplicity of partly overlapping functions. It denotes a phenomenological category of ordinary experiences (e.g. Sue Reference Sue2010a; Pérez Huber and Solorzano Reference Pérez Huber and Solorzano2015), a variety of clinical misbehavior (e.g. Sue et al. Reference Sue, Capodilupo, Torino, Bucceri, Holder, Nadal and Esquilin2007; Freeman and Stewart Reference Freeman and Stewart2018), a cause of health disparities (e.g. Torres, Driscoll, and Burrow Reference Torres, Driscoll and Burrow2010; Gee and Ford Reference Gee and Ford2011), an object of psychological research (e.g. Lau and Williams Reference Lau, Williams and Sue2010; Wong et al. Reference Wong, Derthick, David, Saw and Okazaki2014; Williams Reference Williams2020), and a category deserving of special moral attention (e.g. Friedlaender Reference Friedlaender2018; McTernan Reference McTernan2018; Rini Reference Rini2021). Other researchers have examined how to refine the extension of “microaggression” (e.g. Rini Reference Rini, Freeman and Schroer2020; Thompson Reference Thompson, Freeman and Schroer2020), but in this paper I am concerned with the assumptions that facilitate inquiry about microaggressions.
Projects of inquiry with different aims are often served by different assumptions. In particular, there has been excellent work on the ethics of microaggressions, including Regina Rini’s (2021) account, that is successful in part because it sidesteps less productive kinds of social controversy. Rini’s account and others like it are crafted with assumptions that accommodate the epistemic limitations of individuals, so that the accounts can be applied more straightforwardly in individual deliberation and daily life. However, in empirical research about populations, the same assumptions are less motivated and serve to artificially foreclose empirical possibilities. I argue that some research projects—particularly those that concern causal effects in populations—are better served by a different account of microaggressions.
In section 2, I will say more about research concerning microaggressions in public health and population contexts. In section 3, I will defend a “structural” account of microaggression from criticism by Rini. My arguments do not imply that Rini is mistaken about the ethics of microaggressions, only that the scope of her arguments is limited to some projects and not others. In section 4 I will sketch a framework for thinking of microaggressions in structural terms, illustrated with an example of extant research that aligns with my recommended approach. Finally, I will address some caveats about how my discussion reflects on other microaggression research (section 5) before concluding (section 6).
2. The explanatory project
The term “microaggression” originally denoted acts of subtle hostility or disdain for Black Americans (Pierce Reference Pierce and Barbour1970), but is now understood to refer more broadly to a variety of acts and states of affairs that demean or alienate any oppressed social group or its members (Sue Reference Sue and Wing2010b). The most famous gloss is that
… microaggressions are brief and commonplace daily verbal, behavioral, and environmental indignities, whether intentional or unintentional, that communicate hostile, derogatory, or negative … slights and insults to the target person or group. (Sue et al. Reference Sue, Capodilupo, Torino, Bucceri, Holder, Nadal and Esquilin2007, 273)
The modern microaggression concept applies broadly to many forms of discrimination (including racism, sexism, ableism, classism, queer- and transphobia, colorism, fat-shaming, etc. as well as, of course, intersectional discrimination; Crenshaw Reference Crenshaw1989; Nadal et al. Reference Nadal, Davidoff, Davis, Wong, Marshall and McKenzie2015; Olkin et al. Reference Olkin, Hayward, Abbene and VanHeel2019). Microaggressions are generally understood to be asymmetric in that they necessarily target oppressed social groups or their members, not privileged social groups. The label is only invoked for those slights and transgressions that are “congruent” (Liao and Huebner Reference Liao and Huebner2020, 100) with systems of structural oppression. (Rini (Reference Rini, Freeman and Schroer2020) suggests that microaggressions are “micro” not in the sense that they are small, but in the sense that they are parts of larger patterns.)
This alignment of microaggressions with oppressive systems features prominently in common motivations for psychological research on microaggressions. In particular, it is common for research articles to cite various population-level studies on the negative health effects of discrimination. Negative somatic and psychological health outcomes are correlated with perceived discrimination (Mays, Cochran, and Barnes Reference Mays, Cochran and Barnes2007; Carter Reference Carter2007; Okazaki Reference Okazaki2009; Torres, Driscoll, and Burrow Reference Torres, Driscoll and Burrow2010; Gee and Ford Reference Gee and Ford2011; Hurd et al. Reference Hurd, Varner, Caldwell and Zimmerman2014; Hollingsworth et al. Reference Hollingsworth, Cole, O’Keefe, Tucker, Story and Wingate2017) and not fully explained by other factors such as socioeconomic status or self-esteem (Gee, Spencer, Chen, Yip, et al. Reference Gee, Michael Spencer, Yip and Takeuchi2007; Gee, Spencer, Chen, and Takeuchi Reference Gee, Spencer, Chen and Takeuchi2007). Racial health gaps in the U.S. are the most studied in this context. Microaggressions are commonly thought to play a role in creating and perpetuating these health gaps. However, the mechanisms by which microaggressions contribute to disparate health outcomes are not yet well understood, and different possible mechanisms suggest different mitigating interventions. For example, if microaggressions act on health by way of blood pressure then there are well-studied pharmaceutical and behavioral interventions available, whereas if microaggressions act on health by some other mechanism then these interventions will likely be ineffective.
Frederick W. Gooding, Jr. and I (Akagi and Gooding Reference Akagi and Gooding2021) use the term explanatory microaggressions to refer to the causal factors that explain recalcitrant outcome gaps, which are gaps between oppressed and privileged groups in desirable outcomes (e.g. somatic and mental health, professional attainment, well-being) that are not explained by relative access to material resources or goods. By contrast, hermeneutical microaggressions are the familiar category of denigrating and exclusionary experiences that are frequently called “microaggressions.” While the primary role of the former explanatory category is to explain social outcomes, the latter category helps us make sense of the lived experiences of people who are members of oppressed social groups (cf. Fricker Reference Fricker2007). If the microaggression concept is empirically valuable, we should expect some conceptual cleavages like the distinction between explanatory and hermeneutical microaggressions. This sort of complexity is not evidence of incoherence, as some critics (e.g. Lilienfeld Reference Lilienfeld2017) have suggested; it is a typical feature of scientific concepts (Akagi Reference Akagi2018; Haueis Reference Haueisforthcoming; Novick and Haueis Reference Novick and Haueis2023).
My focus in this paper is on what I call the “explanatory project”: the empirical project of studying microaggressions in the explanatory sense above, discerning the mechanisms that cause recalcitrant outcome gaps, and discovering which kinds of behaviors and situations contribute to them (since they might not be the same behaviors and situations that we call microaggressions in the hermeneutical sense). The explanatory project might be distinguished from other microaggression research projects, such as the hermeneutical projects of better understanding the nature and variety of hermeneutical microaggressions or of constructing anti-oppressive phenomenologies (e.g. Solorzano Reference Solorzano1998; Pérez Huber and Solorzano Reference Pérez Huber and Solorzano2015; Freeman and Stewart Reference Freeman and Stewart2018), or the ethical project of correctly assigning responsibility and blame for microaggressions (e.g. Friedlaender Reference Friedlaender2018; McTernan Reference McTernan2018; Rini Reference Rini2021), or the management project of fostering near-term institutional reform given the limitations of our current understanding and social structures.
3. Explanatory microaggressions as structural
Microaggression researchers and scholars engage in these research projects using a variety of disciplinary methods. They have offered various conflicting accounts of what microaggressions are and how to properly ascribe them. Emma McClure and Regina Rini (McClure and Rini Reference McClure and Rini2020; Rini Reference Rini2021) identify three styles of accounts. First, motivational or psychological accounts define microaggressions based on the (perhaps unconscious) psychological states of a microaggression performer (e.g. Pierce Reference Pierce and Barbour1970; Sue et al. Reference Sue, Capodilupo, Torino, Bucceri, Holder, Nadal and Esquilin2007; Dotson Reference Dotson2011; Tschaepe Reference Tschaepe2016; Lilienfeld Reference Lilienfeld2017). Second, experiential accounts define microaggressions based on the phenomenological states of a microaggression target (Rini Reference Rini, Freeman and Schroer2020, Reference Rini2021; Fatima Reference Fatima, Cole and Hassel2017; Sue Reference Sue2017; see also Crocker and Major Reference Crocker and Major1989). Third, structural accounts define microaggressions based on their functional or causal role in an oppressive social system (e.g. Pérez Huber and Solorzano Reference Pérez Huber and Solorzano2015; Friedlaender Reference Friedlaender2018; McTernan Reference McTernan2018; Freeman and Stewart Reference Freeman and Stewart2018; Williams Reference Williams2020). Hybrid accounts might combine elements from these three basic styles.
While projects and account styles appear in many combinations in the existing literature, structural accounts are naturally suited to the explanatory project. After all, the goal of the explanatory project is to understand the causal mechanisms of social outcome gaps, and structural accounts identify microaggressions by their causal roles in social processes. However, Rini offers two arguments against structural accounts of microaggressions. First, she suggests that structural accounts obscure what it is that makes blame difficult to assign for microaggressions (2021, 81, 92–4). While this consideration is germane to Rini’s ethical project, correctly assigning blame is not a central concern of the explanatory project and I will not comment on this argument here.
Rini’s other argument appeals to standpoint epistemology and, in particular, the folly of holding a revisionist view on which members of oppressed social groups (potential microaggression targets) might be commonly mistaken about microaggressions. If structural accounts ascribe microaggressions on the basis of their causal role, rather than on the experiences of microaggression targets, it is inevitable that defenders of structural accounts will disagree with microaggression targets about at least some cases (and perhaps about many or most). This consequence is undesirable. Rini writes:
Does anyone have the standing to tell people who welcome a social practice that they are unwittingly accepting their own subjugation or are complicit in their own oppression? … we should defer as much as possible to people’s own experiences. I certainly don’t think that I, as a white person, am in any position to tell a Black woman who loves people asking to touch her hair that she is misperceiving her social relations. (Rini Reference Rini2021, 80; see also Rini Reference Rini, Freeman and Schroer2020, 108–113)
On structural accounts, microaggressions “cannot be confidently applied in the world without god-like knowledge” that is, at best, inaccessible to most of us most of the time (2020, 109). Inquirers—some of whom will occupy privileged social positions—would be put in the unsavory position of dictating to putative microaggression targets whether some act or state of affairs is a genuine microaggression. Besides, “nothing alienates a potential ally more quickly than insisting you understand her life better than she does” (Rini Reference Rini2021, 80). For these reasons, Rini favors an experiential account that allows inquirers to avoid disagreeing with potential microaggression targets.
Rini’s argument here is well suited to her ethical project, but it turns on considerations that need not hold the same weight for the explanatory project. It is indeed awkward and rhetorically ineffective to disagree with people about their own experiences, and this fact should constrain accounts that must be applied in interpersonal conversations or daily life. For an ethical project like Rini’s, it is a problem if we can never or rarely say with confidence, of some specific situation, that a microaggression occurred. Such an inability would frustrate attempts to correctly assign blame to individual agents. However, the explanatory project does not require us to ascribe microaggressions in everyday contexts. It is not inappropriate for medical scientists to investigate genes or internal anatomical structures just because they cannot be readily identified in typical interpersonal interactions. Likewise, it is not inappropriate for an account of explanatory microaggressions to countenance criteria of ascription that are difficult to apply in daily life, or that are politically inexpedient. In both cases, we inquire into covert causes in the hope that our discoveries might yield knowledge that eases suffering and promotes human flourishing. If our goal is to intervene in the causes of outcome gaps, it is sufficient to discover interventions that work at a population level. For example, we might discourage some category of behavior without having to know exactly which acts contribute to outcome gaps, or we might encourage behaviors (such as affinity group activities) that moderate the harmful effects of microaggressions. By analogy, we are justified in regulating automobile travel with speed limits and safety features without knowing in advance precisely which driver actions would have otherwise caused collisions.
The revisionist potential of structuralism about microaggressions is a drawback for the ethical project because it conflicts with some versions of standpoint theory, but this conflict need not arise in the explanatory project. Standpoint epistemologists hold that members of oppressed social groups typically understand some topics better than other people, particularly their own experiences and the ways they are affected by oppressive systems. Standpoint theorists do not claim that members of oppressed social groups have any sort of automatic or total knowledge (Wylie Reference Wylie, Figueroa and Harding2003; Freeman and Stewart Reference Freeman, Stewart, Freeman and Schroer2020), and certainly not unchallengeable knowledge of the detailed causal mechanisms of unconscious, distributed physiological and psychological processes whose effects, while significant, are discernible only through quantitative empirical studies. Revisionism in this context is no vice, even for standpoint theorists.
Moreover, the same factors that are flaws for the ethical project may be virtues for the explanatory project. For example, a structural account that countenances revisionism has the potential to contribute to our understanding of phenomena such as false consciousness (see, e.g., Bartky Reference Bartky1990; Khader Reference Khader2012; cf. Rini Reference Rini2021, 80). And whereas Rini’s account would have been toothless without a clear criterion for identifying (hermeneutical) microaggressions, I cannot offer such a criterion for explanatory microaggressions, apart from the vague requirement that they explain recalcitrant outcome gaps, because a more precise account of the causal role of explanatory microaggressions must be discovered empirically.
In summary, accounts such as Rini’s are crafted to accommodate, rather than to overcome, our present epistemic limitations. In particular, many extant accounts (especially in the context of ethical or hermeneutical projects) take as given various social controversies or gaps in our understanding of microaggressions and their causal contribution to outcome gaps. Such accounts are useful, but limited by epistemic constraints that apply to individuals, not to research programs. To apply the same assumptions in the explanatory project would artificially foreclose empirical possibilities about what kinds of behaviors or situations contribute to outcome gaps, and whether these contributors are dissociable from the experiences of their targets. Whereas it is proper for an account that is intended for everyday application to be constrained by the epistemic limits of individuals, an account that is meant to facilitate inquiry into heretofore hidden causes should not accede to those limits but seek to overcome them.
4. A framework for structural microaggression research
So how might a structural account help us to conceptualize microaggressions for the explanatory project, and discover clearer criteria for identifying them? We currently have a limited understanding of the causal mechanisms of recalcitrant outcome gaps, so organizing our knowledge of explanatory microaggressions in terms of their causal role helps us to confront the limits of our current understanding. It may also serve to remind us that the mechanisms underlying outcome gaps may be quite heterogeneous. Ideally, research in the explanatory project can be located relative to four dimensions: (a) causes (specific situations/behaviors, i.e. explanatory microaggressions), (b) effects (negative outcomes), (c) populations (social groups), and (d) mechanistic hypotheses.
Regarding (a) causes, the most familiar typology of microaggressions is Derald Wing Sue and colleagues’ (2007) microassaults, microinsults, and microinvalidations. Lauren Freeman and Heather Stewart (2018) suggest an alternative, clinical typology based on psychological effects: epistemic, emotional, and self-identity microaggressions. The behaviors, situations, and themes covered in these typologies are quite diverse, so research should be specific regarding precisely which behaviors and situations are being investigated. In the long run, such specificity in the literature would allow us to more precisely discern the extension of explanatory microaggressions.
Following Freeman and Stewart’s lead, we might strive to categorize explanatory microaggressions by their (b) effects, and specifically on the outcomes that they influence: microaggressions that affect somatic health, mental health, professional attainment, etc. These categories can be further subdivided into more specific effects, e.g. microaggressions contributing to anxiety (Gee, Spencer, Chen, Yip, et al. Reference Gee, Michael Spencer, Yip and Takeuchi2007), suicidality (Hollingsworth et al. Reference Hollingsworth, Cole, O’Keefe, Tucker, Story and Wingate2017), heart disease (Gee, Spencer, Chen, and Takeuchi Reference Gee, Spencer, Chen and Takeuchi2007), etc. Cross-cutting these categories, it is likely that effects vary between (c) populations, i.e. social groups (including intersectional sub-groups) and societies.
As for the (d) mechanisms through which microaggressions contribute to outcome gaps, there are currently many hypotheses. Cameron Evans and Ron Mallon (Reference Evans, Mallon, Freeman and Schroer2020) distinguish “accumulation” and “stochastic” mechanisms. Physiologically, past research has explored the possibility that microaggressions contribute to health outcomes via stress or cortisol (Carter Reference Carter2007; S. P. Harrell Reference Harrell2000), or via hypertension (J. P. Harrell, Hall, and Taliaferro Reference Harrell, Hall and Taliaferro2003), or via epigenetics (Kuzawa and Sweet Reference Kuzawa and Sweet2009; Goosby and Heidbrink Reference Goosby and Heidbrink2013; Aroke et al. Reference Aroke, Joseph, Abhrarup Roy, Overstreet, Vance and Goodin2019). Psychological hypotheses about the causal role of microaggressions include motivational factors such as implicit bias (Pierce Reference Pierce and Barbour1970; Sue et al. Reference Sue, Capodilupo, Torino, Bucceri, Holder, Nadal and Esquilin2007), experiential factors such as attributional ambiguity (Rini Reference Rini2021; Crocker and Major Reference Crocker and Major1989) and attributions to prejudice (Branscombe, Schmitt, and Harvey Reference Branscombe, Schmitt and Harvey1999), and structural factors such as generational trauma (Goosby and Heidbrink Reference Goosby and Heidbrink2013) and plausible deniability of discrimination (McTernan Reference McTernan2018; Friedlaender Reference Friedlaender2018). Of course, these hypotheses are not mutually exclusive. Some combination of these explanations may turn out to be correct, either between (social group, outcome gap) pairs or within them.
Studies on explanatory microaggressions contribute to our knowledge by addressing some region within this four-dimensional space. For example, a study by Lucas Torres, Mark Driscoll, and Anthony Burrow (2010) examined (b) mental health outcomes, and specifically depressive symptoms, among (c) Black American graduate students, focusing on (d) the stress hypothesis. First, a qualitative experiment examined common themes in participant responses, identifying (a) three themes of interest: underestimations of ability, assumptions of criminality/second-class citizen (both corresponding to microinsult themes identified in Sue et al. Reference Sue, Capodilupo, Torino, Bucceri, Holder, Nadal and Esquilin2007), and cultural/racial isolation. Then the researchers performed quantitative experiments to assess the incidence of microaggressions with these themes for their study participants as well as participant stress levels, depressive symptoms, and coping strategies. Torres, Driscoll, and Burrow found a moderated-mediational model on which microaggressions contribute to depressive symptoms, mediated by stress and moderated by “active coping” strategies. Studies like this one contribute clearly to the explanatory project by situating themselves in the four-dimensional space of causes, effects, populations, and mechanisms.
5. Are explanatory microaggressions really microaggressions?
Before concluding, I will discuss some worries that one might have about the view defended here and its relation to other work on microaggressions.
I defended the revisionist potential of structuralism for the explanatory project (section 3), but one might worry that this potential could obliterate the extensional overlap between explanatory and hermeneutical microaggressions. That is, if explanatory microaggressions are just whatever it is that causes outcome gaps, then they could turn out to be very different sorts of things than familiar examples of microaggressions. Perhaps, for example, we may discover that insinuations that queerness is unnatural do not contribute to health gaps, and therefore that such slights are not really (explanatory) microaggressions. If that is even possible, then might it not be infelicitous to say that the explanatory project is really about microaggressions at all?
I am willing to bite the bullet here: explanatory microaggressions might not resemble hermeneutical microaggressions, and little hangs on whether we use the word “microaggression.” But I temper my ambivalence with the following considerations. First, it is quite plausible that explanatory and hermeneutical microaggressions do have significant extensional overlap. After all, it is quite common for researchers to motivate discussions of (hermeneutical) microaggressions by appealing to outcome gaps, so it is a common belief among microaggression researchers that (hermeneutical) microaggressions will turn out to fulfill the causal role of explanatory microaggressions. Second, there is an existing body of research about the health effects of microaggressions, sometimes in contrast to other forms of prejudice or discrimination. So my choice of terminology is intended to follow the lead of empirical researchers. Finally, the various microaggression research projects (explanatory, hermeneutical, and ethical) are interrelated. Explanatory research about microaggressions is grounded in hermeneutical methods (e.g. the qualitative element in Torres, Driscoll, and Burrow Reference Torres, Driscoll and Burrow2010), and would benefit from further grounding in, e.g., community science (Thompson Reference Thompson, Freeman and Schroer2020). Ethical evaluation of microaggressions depends in part on the ways that they contribute to harms such as outcome gaps (as well as other harms). So, while I think it is worthwhile to distinguish between these various kinds of project, there is value in allowing the word “microaggression” to develop distinct but related senses.
One might also worry that my structural proposal could be self-eliminating. That is, we may discover that explanatory microaggressions are so mechanistically heterogeneous that they are not worth grouping together under a common label. This is a possibility that depends in part on empirical facts and in part on the linguistic decisions of future researchers, neither of which can be predicted with great confidence. In the meantime, I would contend that the explanatory project is well served by structuralist assumptions for the reasons provided above. And I would hasten to add that eliminativism about explanatory microaggressions does not imply eliminativism about hermeneutical microaggressions. Even if a structural account of explanatory microaggressions ultimately fails due to the heterogeneity of causal roles, there will continue to be value in considering microaggressions as a hermeneutical resource or as a category for moral evaluation.
6. Conclusion
I have argued that different investigative projects regarding microaggressions can require different assumptions about the nature of microaggressions. In particular, whereas a structural account of microaggressions might be inappropriate for an ethical inquiry like Rini’s, the considerations she raises do not apply to the explanatory project of understanding the mechanisms that cause structural outcome gaps such as the racial health gap in the U.S. Likewise, my defense of structuralism for the explanatory project has no straightforward bearing on Rini’s project. I also sketched how thinking of (explanatory) microaggressions in terms of their causal role can help us to categorize microaggressions and remain mindful of the possibility that microaggressions contribute to outcome gaps in diverse ways.
As our understanding of microaggressions and structural oppression matures, we should be prepared to embrace complexity and contextualism. Microaggressions may manifest differently not only relative to social groups, societies, and contexts, but relative to epistemic aims and research projects. Different projects may demand different styles of account if they are subject to different constraints on methods and application. Inquiry is stifled by an insistence that accounts, definitions, and assumptions be consistent across research projects.
Acknowledgments
I am grateful for feedback and discussion from many people, especially Morgan Thompson, Shen-yi Liao, Kareem Khalifa, Daniel James, Frederick W. Gooding, Jr., and participants at the 2022 Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association.