Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-19T02:58:52.635Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Responsiveness and Robustness in the David Lewis Signaling Game

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

We consider modifications to the standard David Lewis signaling game and relax a number of unrealistic implicit assumptions that are often built into the framework. In particular, we motivate and explore various asymmetries that exist between the sender and receiver roles. We find that endowing receivers with a more realistic set of responses significantly decreases the likelihood of signaling, while allowing for unequal selection pressure often has the opposite effect. We argue that the results of this article can also help make sense of a well-known evolutionary puzzle regarding the absence of an evolutionary arms race between sender and receiver in conflict-of-interest signaling games.

Type
Biology
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

We thank Kim Sterelny, Ron Planer, and the audiences at the Sydney-ANU Philosophy of Biology Workshop, the Australasian Association of Philosophy 2016 conference, the ANU Evo Theory reading group, and the 2016 Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association.

References

Bruner, Justin, O’Connor, Cailin, Rubin, Hannah, and Huttegger, Simon M. 2014. “David Lewis in the Lab: Experimental Results on the Emergence of Meaning.” Synthese, September, 1–19.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R., and Krebs, J. R. 1979. “Arms Races between and within Species.” Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B 205 (1161): 489511.Google ScholarPubMed
Godfrey-Smith, Peter, and Martínez, Manolo. 2013. “Communication and Common Interest.” PLoS Computational Biology 9 (11): e1003282.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hobaiter, Catherine, and Byrne, Richard W. 2014. “The Meanings of Chimpanzee Gestures.” Current Biology 24 (14): 15961600.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hofbauer, Josef, and Huttegger, Simon M. 2008. “Feasibility of Communication in Binary Signaling Games.” Journal of Theoretical Biology 254 (4): 843–49.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Huttegger, Simon M. 2007. “Evolution and the Explanation of Meaning.” Philosophy of Science 74 (1): 127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David K. 1969. Convention: A Philosophical Study. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Martínez, Manolo, and Godfrey-Smith, Peter. 2016. “Common Interest and Signaling Games: A Dynamic Analysis.” Philosophy of Science 83 (3): 371–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Owren, Michael J., Rendall, Drew, and Ryan, Michael J. 2010. “Redefining Animal Signaling: Influence versus Information in Communication.” Biology and Philosophy 25 (5): 755–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pawlowitsch, Christina. 2008. “Why Evolution Does Not Always Lead to an Optimal Signaling System.” Games and Economic Behavior 63 (1): 203–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seyfarth, Robert M., and Cheney, Dorothy L. 2003. “Signalers and Receivers in Animal Communication.” Annual Review of Psychology 54 (1): 145–73.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Skyrms, Brian. 1996. Evolution of the Social Contract. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skyrms, Brian 2010. Signals: Evolution, Learning, and Information. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterelny, Kim. 2012. “A Glass Half-Full: Brian Skyrms’s Signals.” Economics and Philosophy 28 (1): 7386.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Valen, L. 1973. “A New Evolutionary Law.” Evolutionary Theory 1:130.Google Scholar