Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-wpx69 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-12T16:49:27.512Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reflections on the Problem of Time in Relation to Neurophysiology and Psychology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2022

Extract

In a previous paper it was suggested that specific concepts are needed in the psychological sciences and the basic mental triad was described as a useful tool to further our understanding of mentation (1). It was stated that the sensori-motor reflex principle cannot describe and explain mental phenomena, because the reflex is basically a mechanistic occurrence, while mental phenomena differ in essence from mechanisms. Since conditioned reflexes can be conceived as sensori-motor reflexes with another, non-mechanistic factor superimposed, similarities and contrasts between reflexes and conditioned reflexes were taken as the material from which one can develop new thoughts about mentation. Reflex shutting of the eyelid, caused by direct contact between cornea and a small, invisible foreign body was compared with and contrasted to shutting the eye before a large, visible object thrusting toward the eye. It was shown that reflexes occur in response to a stimulus after the stimulus has been applied, while conditioned reflexes seem to anticipate the stimulus. This was taken as evidence that conditioned reflexes have a protensive character, have a relationship to the future, which sensori-motor reflexes lack. This difference in time relationship was developed into the statement that the difference between mechanisms and mental phenomena lies in their different relationship to the future. The need for specific concepts to describe mental phenomena stems from the inability of the reflex principle to deal with the protensive tendency of mental phenomena and to fill this need the concept of the basic mental triad was offered. This principle consists of three interdependent, interwoven phases: the triad connects with the past through condensation of some of the subject's past experience into a vaguely formed conglomerate; it connects with the future by projecting the condensed past into the future; the central phase of the triad is the act within the present instant, where a synthesis of past, present and future is accomplished.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1952

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Moulyn, Adrian C., “Mechanisms and Mental Phenomena,” Phil. of Sci., Vol. 14, No. 3, July 1947, pp. 242253.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
2. Toynbee, Arnold J., A Study of History, Abridgement by Somervell, D. C., Oxford University Press, New York and London, 1947, p. 60.Google Scholar
3. Rickert, Heinrich, Die Grenzen der naturwissenschaftlichen Begriffsbildung (The limitations of natural scientific concept formation); Tübingen, 1921, Mohr.Google Scholar
4. Rickert, Heinrich, Psychophysische Causalität und psychophysischer Parallelismus, in: Philosophische Abhandlungen, 1900, p. 84.Google Scholar
5. Von Mises, Richard, Ueber das naturwissenschaftliche Weltbild der Gegenwart, in: Naturwissenschaften, 18er Jahrgang, Heft 43.10.1007/BF01488978CrossRefGoogle Scholar
6. Yakovlev, Paul I., “Motility, Behavior and the Brain,” Journal of Nervous and Mental Diseases, April 1948, Vol. 107, No. 4, p. 318.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
7. Fearing, Franklin, Reflex Action, A study in the history of physiological psychology; Williams and Wilkins, Baltimore, 1930, p. 20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
8. Pavlov, Ivan P., Conditioned Reflexes, Oxford University Press, 1927, p. 25.Google Scholar
9. Clay, E. R., The Alternative, MacMillan & Co., London 1882, p. 167.Google Scholar
10. James, William, Principles of Psychology, Vol. I, p. 609; New York, Henry Holt.Google Scholar
11. Bergson, Henri, Essai sur les Données immédiates de la conscience, 53e Edition, Presse Universitaire de France, Paris 1946, p. 74.Google Scholar
12. Jordan, H. J., “Causality and totality of biological phenomena, ”Nederlandsch Tijdschrift voor Geneeskunde, Vol. 79, II, June 1, 1935, pp. 26952708.Google Scholar
13. Goldstein, Kurt, Der Aufbau des Organismus, Martinus Nijhoff, Hague, Holland, 1934, p. 243 (quotat. translated by author).10.1007/978-94-017-7141-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
14. Weiss, Paul, Nature and Man, New York, Henry Holt, 1947, p. 53.Google Scholar
15. Yerkes, Robert M., “The intelligence of earthworms,” Journal of Animal Behavior, Vol. 2, 1912, p. 334.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
16. Bergson, Henri, Matière et Mémoire, Félix Alcan, Paris, 1925, 20e Edition, p. 204.Google Scholar
17. Mayo, Katherine, Mother India, Blue Ribbon Books, New York, p. 379.Google Scholar
18. Straus, Erwin, Vom Sinn der Sinne.Google Scholar
19. Moulyn, Adrian C., The limitations of mechanistic methods in the biological sciences,“ Scientific Monthly, Vol. LXXI, No. 1, July, 1950, pp. 4449.Google Scholar