Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-vdxz6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T06:01:13.007Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Politics of Postmodern Philosophy of Science

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Joseph Rouse*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy Wesleyan University
*
Send reprint requests to the author, Department of Philosophy, Wesleyan University, Middletown, CT 06457.

Abstract

Modernism in the philosophy of science demands a unified story about what makes an inquiry scientific (or a successful science). Fine's “natural ontological attitude” (NOA) is “postmodern” in joining trust in local scientific practice with suspicion toward any global interpretation of science to legitimate or undercut that trust. I consider four readings of this combination of trust and suspicion and their consequences for the autonomy and cultural credibility of the sciences. Three readings take respectively Fine's trusting attitude, his emphasis upon local practice, and his antiessentialism about science as most fundamental to NOA. A fourth, more adequate reading, prompted by recent feminist interpretations of science, offers less restrictive readings of both Fine's trust and his suspicion toward approaching science with “ready-made philosophical engines” (Fine 1986b, 177).

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1991 The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I would like to thank Mark Stone and Margaret Crouch, who offered very helpful comments upon an earlier draft of this paper; the two anonymous referees for Philosophy of Science, whose reports prompted several significant clarifications and extensions of the argument; and the audiences to whom I presented versions of it at the University of Connecticut, the College of William and Mary, and Oberlin College. The paper is an outgrowth of a presentation to Arthur Fine's National Endowment for the Humanities Summer Seminar in 1987, and I thank Professor Fine and the Endowment for their support.

References

Boyd, R. (1984), “The Current Status of Scientific Realism”, in J. Leplin (ed.), Scientific Realism. Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 4182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, N. (1983), How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, A. (1986a), The Shaky Game: Einstein, Realism and the Quantum Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Fine, A. (1986b), “Unnatural Attitudes: Realist and Instrumentalist Attachments to Science”, Mind 95: 149179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, A. (forthcoming), “Science Made Up: Constructivist Sociology of Scientific Knowledge”, in P. Galison and D. Stump (eds.), Disunity and Contextualism in the Philosophy of Science. Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Fraser, N. and Nicholson, L. (1988), “Social Criticism without Philosophy: An Encounter between Feminism and Postmodernism”, in A. Ross (ed.), Universal Abandon? The Politics of Postmodernism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 83104.Google Scholar
Fuller, S. (1988), Social Epistemology. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Galison, P. (1987), How Experiments End. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Galison, P. (1988), “History, Philosophy, and the Central Metaphor”, Science in Context 2: 197211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginzberg, R. (1987), “Uncovering Gynocentric Science”, Hypatia 2: 89106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffin, S. (1978), Woman and Nature: The Roaring inside Her. 1st ed. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Hacking, I. (1983), Representing and Intervening: Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of Natural Science. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harding, S. (1986), The Science Question in Feminism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Hesse, M. (1980), “In Defense of Objectivity”, in M. Hesse, Revolutions and Reconstructions in the Philosophy of Science. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, pp. 167186.Google Scholar
Hrdy, S. B. (1981), The Woman That Never Evolved. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Irigaray, L. and Bove, C. M. (tr.) (1987), “Le sujet de la science est-il sexué?/Is the Subject of Science Sexed?Hypatia 2: 6587.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keller, E. F. (1985), Reflections on Gender and Science. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Lyotard, J. F. (1984), The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. Translated by Bennington, G. and Massumi, B. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, A. (1980), “Epistemological Crises, Dramatic Narrative, and the Philosophy of Science”, in G. Gutting (ed.), Paradigms and Revolutions: Appraisals and Applications of Thomas Kuhn's Philosophy of Science. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 5474.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, A. (1981), After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Rorty, R. (1982), Consequences of Pragmatism: Essays, 1972–1980. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Rouse, J. (1987), Knowledge and Power: Toward a Political Philosophy of Science. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Rouse, J. (1991), “Philosophy of Science and the Persistent Narratives of Modernity”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 22: 141162.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapere, D. (1984), Reason and the Search for Knowledge: Investigations in the Philosophy of Science. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Shapere, D. (1986), “External and Internal Factors in the Development of Science”, Science and Technology Studies 4: 19, 19–23.Google Scholar
Tuana, N. (ed.) (1988), “Feminism and Science II”, Hypatia 3: 1168.CrossRefGoogle Scholar