Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-vdxz6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T05:06:15.364Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Perception and Belief: A Regress Problem

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Paul K. Moser*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Loyola University of Chicago

Extract

What has belief to do with perception? Some contemporary philosophers have suggested that one's perceiving an object entails one's having a particular perceptual belief, not just some belief or other, about that object. N. R. Hanson, for instance, has illustrated the present view, with respect to visual perception, as follows:

What is it to see boxes, staircases, birds, antelopes, bears, goblets, X-ray tubes? It is (at least) to have knowledge of certain sorts. … It is to see that, were certain things done to objects before our eyes, other things would result. … To see an X-ray tube is at least to see that, were it dropped on stone, it would smash. … Seeing a bird in the sky involves seeing that it will not suddenly do vertical snap rolls; and this is more than marks the retina. (Hanson 1958, pp. 20–21)

Type
Discussion
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association 1986

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am grateful to Harry Gensler, Kevin Flannery, and two referees of Philosophy of Science for helpful comments on some earlier versions of this article.

References

Burge, Tyler (1977), “Belief De Re”, Journal of Philosophy 74: 338–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ducasse, C. J. (1968), “Objectivity, Objective Reference, and Perception”, in Truth, Knowledge, and Causation. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Hanson, N. R. (1958), Patterns of Discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hanson, N. R. (1969), Perception and Discovery. San Francisco: Freeman, Cooper, and Company.Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul (1980), Naming and Necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lynn, Richard (1966), Attention, Arousal, and the Orientation Reaction. Oxford: Pergamon Press.Google Scholar
Malcolm, Norman (1963), “Direct Perception”, in Knowledge and Certainty. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1959), “Proof of an External World”, in Philosophical Papers. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Moser, Paul (1984), “A Defense of Epistemic Intuitionism”, Metaphilosophy 15: 196–209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moser, Paul. (1985), Empirical Justification. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Mostofsky, David (1970), “The Semantics of Attention”, in Attention: Contemporary Theory and Analysis, Mostofsky, D. (ed.). New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand (1940), An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth. London: George Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
Ryle, Gilbert (1949), The Concept of Mind. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar