Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-lnqnp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T00:58:45.592Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Ontology of Patterns in Empirical Data

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

This article defends the following claims. First, for patterns exhibited in empirical data, there is no criterion on which to demarcate patterns that are physically significant and patterns that are not physically significant. I call a pattern physically significant if it corresponds to a structure in the world. Second, all patterns must be regarded as physically significant. Third, distinct patterns must be regarded as providing evidence for distinct structures in the world. Fourth, in consequence, the world must be conceived as showing all possible structures.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I presented a previous version of this article in the “Phenomena, Data, and Patterns” symposium at the Twenty-first Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Pittsburgh, November 2008. I thank the other speakers, James Bogen, Katherine Brading, Paul Teller, and James Woodward; our chair, James Robert Brown; and the audience for a lively and enjoyable session. I also thank Anjan Chakravartty and a second, unnamed referee of this journal for useful comments.

References

Bogen, James. 2010. “Noise in the World.” Philosophy of Science, in this issue.10.1086/656006CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bogen, James, and Woodward, James. 1988. “Saving the Phenomena.” Philosophical Review 97:303–52.10.2307/2185445CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brading, Katherine. 2010. “Autonomous Patterns and Scientific Realism.” Philosophy of Science, in this issue.10.1086/656816CrossRefGoogle Scholar
György, Buzsáki. 2006. Rhythms of the Brain. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dickey, Jean O. 1995. “Earth Rotation Variations from Hours to Centuries.” In Highlights of Astronomy, Vol. 10, ed. Appenzeller, Immo, 1744. Dordrecht: Kluwer.10.1007/978-94-010-9374-3_2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodman, Nelson. 1983. Fact, Fiction, and Forecast. 4th ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McAllister, James W. 1997. “Phenomena and Patterns in Data Sets.” Erkenntnis 47:217–28.10.1023/A:1005387021520CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McAllister, James W.. 2003. “Algorithmic Randomness in Empirical Data.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 34:633–46.10.1016/S0039-3681(03)00047-5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McAllister, James W.. 2007. “Model Selection and the Multiplicity of Patterns in Empirical Data.” Philosophy of Science 74:884–94.10.1086/525630CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McAllister, James W.. 2009. “What Do Patterns in Empirical Data Tell Us about the Structure of the World?” Synthese. Published electronically July 7, doi:10.1007/s11229-009-9613-x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, Wesley C. 1984. Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Teller, Paul. 2010. “‘Saving the Phenomena’ Today.” Philosophy of Science, in this issue.10.1086/656537CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodward, James. 1989. “Data and Phenomena.” Synthese 79:393472.10.1007/BF00869282CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodward, James. 2010. “Data, Phenomena, Signal, and Noise.” Philosophy of Science, in this issue.10.1086/656554CrossRefGoogle Scholar