Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dlnhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T06:41:42.568Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On Species Individualism: A New Defense of the Species-as-Individuals Hypothesis

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Keith A. Coleman
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy
E. O. Wiley
Affiliation:
Department of Ecology and Evolutionary Biology and Natural History Museum, The University of Kansas

Abstract

We attempt to defend the species-as-individuals hypothesis by examining the logical role played by the binomials (e.g., “Homo sapiens,” “Pinus ponderosa”) in biological discourse about species. Those who contend that the binomials can be properly understood as functioning in biological theory as singular terms opt for an objectual account of species and view species as individuals. Those who contend that the binomials can in principle be eliminated from biological theory in favor of predicate expressions opt for a predicative account of species and view species as kinds. We contend that biologists' talk about species is talk about species as individuals, and we conclude that the most plausible account of species is an objectual account.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 2001

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Reprints requests to: E. O. Wiley, Natural History Museum, The University of Kansas, Lawrence, KS 66045; email [email protected].

We gratefully acknowledge our indebtedness to Darrell Frost, David Hull, Philip Kitcher, and Elliott Sober, all of whom kindly reviewed earlier drafts of the present manuscript. Thanks also to one anonymous reviewer who suggested that we introduce the term “historical set” in our analysis of Kitcher's position.

References

Apostle, Hipprocrates G. and Gerson, Lloyd P. (1986), Aristotle: Selected Works, 2nd ed. Grinnell, Iowa: The Peripatetic Press, 3033.Google Scholar
Bernier, Réjane (1984), “The Species as an Individual: Facing Essentialism”, Systematic Zoology 33: 460469.10.2307/2413097CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyd, R. (1999), “Homeostasis, Species, and Higher Taxa”, in Wilson, Robert A. (ed.), Species: New Interdisciplinary Essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 141185.Google Scholar
Darwin, Charles (1859), The Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or The Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life. London: John Murray.Google Scholar
Frege, Gottlob ([1884] 1950, 1961), The Foundations of Arithmetic. Translated by J. L. Austin. Originally published as Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik: Eine logisch-mathematische Untersuchung über den Begriff der Zahl (Breslau, 1884). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ghiselin, Michael T. (1966), “On Psychologism on the Logic of Taxonomic Controversies”, Systematic Zoology 15: 207215.10.2307/2411392CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ghiselin, Michael T. (1974), “A Radical Solution to the Species Problem”, Systematic Zoology 23: 536544.10.2307/2412471CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ghiselin, Michael T. (1984), “‘Definition,’ ‘Character,’ and Other Equivocal Terms”, Systematic Zoology 33: 104110.10.2307/2413135CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hennig, Willi (1966), Phylogenetic Systematics. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
Hull, David L. (1964), “Consistency and Monophyly”, Systematic Zoology 13: 111.10.2307/2411431CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, David L. (1966), “The Logical Structure of the Linnaean Hierarchy”, Systematic Zoology 15: 97111.Google Scholar
Hull, David L. (1976), “Are Species Really Individuals?”, Systematic Zoology 25: 174191.10.2307/2412744CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, David L. (1981), “Kitts and Kitts and Caplan on Species”, Philosophy of Science 48: 141152.10.1086/288985CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (1984), “Species”, Philosophy of Science 51: 308333.10.1086/289182CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitts, David B. (1983), “Can Baptism Alone Save a Species?”, Systematic Zoology 32: 2733.10.2307/2413217CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, Saul A. (1971), “Identity and Necessity”, in Munitz, Milton K. (ed.), Identity and Individuation. New York: New York University Press, 135164.Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul A. (1980), Naming and Necessity, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Mayr, Ernst (1982), The Growth of Biological Knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand ([1905] 1967), “On Denoting”, reprinted in Copi, Irving and Gould, James (eds.), Contemporary Readings in Logical Theory. New York: Macmillan, 93105.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard V. (1980), From a Logical Point of View, 2nd ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.10.2307/j.ctv1c5cx5cCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, Willard V. (1986), Philosophy of Logic, 2nd ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2526.Google Scholar
Wiley, E. O. (1981a), Phylogenetics: The Theory and Practice of Phylogenetic Systematics. New York: Wiley-Interscience.Google Scholar
Wiley, E. O. (1981b), “Convex Groups and Consistent Classifications”, Systematic Botany 6: 346358.10.2307/2418447CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wiley, E. O. (1989), “Kinds, Individuals and Theories”, in Ruse, Michael (ed.), What the Philosophy of Biology Is—Essays for David Hull. Hingbam, MA: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 273284.Google Scholar
Wilson, Robert A. (1999), “Realism, Essence, and Kind: Resuscitating Species Essentialism?”, in Wilson, Robert A. (ed.), Species: New Interdisciplinary Essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 187207.10.7551/mitpress/6396.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar