Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gxg78 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T00:45:07.838Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Mill's Unrevised Philosophy of Economics: A Comment on Hausman

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Neil de Marchi*
Affiliation:
Department of Economics, Duke University

Abstract

Hausman has argued that Mill in the Logic demands verification of qualified, inexact statements if they are to be considered lawlike. This puts Mill in line with a reasonable interpretation of what modern microeconomists are about, but requires the additional hypothesis that Mill abandoned his earlier stress on modal truth in his 1836 essay on the method of economics. The paper maintains that neither textual nor contextual evidence supports this hypothesis. Moreover, it is superfluous if one attends carefully to how Mill conceived economic science, which occupied a peculiar, somewhat isolated place in his own views on the deductive method and on verification.

Type
Discussion
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association 1986

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I have benefited greatly from correspondence with Dan Hausman. Uskali Maki, Margaret Schabas, Wade Hands, and Roy Weintraub have made useful comments and corrections for which I am grateful. I am indebted also to an anonymous referee for suggestions towards improving the presentation.

References

Archibald, G. C. (1961), “Chamberlin versus Chicago”, Review of Economic Studies: 128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Archibald, G. C. (1964), “Profit-maximising and Non-Price Competition”, Economica: 1322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blaug, Mark (1980), The Methodology of Economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hahn, F. H. (1973), “The Winter of Our Discontent”, Economica: 322–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, Daniel M. (1981a), “John Stuart Mill's Philosophy of Economics”, Philosophy of Science 48: 363–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, Daniel M. (1981b), “Are General Equilibrium Theories Explanatory?” in Philosophy of Economics, Pitt, J. C. (ed.). Dordrecht: D. Reidel, pp. 1732.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, Daniel M. (ed.) (1984), The Philosophy of Economics: An Anthology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Klant, J. J. (1984), The Rules of the Game: The Logical Structure of Economic Theories. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lange, Oscar (1944), Price Flexibility and Employment. Cowles Commission Monograph No. 8. Bloomington: Principia Press.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. (1963–) The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol. 4, Essays on Economics and Society, containing the essay “On the Definition of Political Economy; and on the Method of Investigation Proper to It”, vol. 7 and 8, A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive, vol. 12, Earlier Letters, 1812–1848. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Morgan, Mary S. (1984), “The History of Econometric Thought: analysis of the main problems of relating economic theory to data in the first half of the twentieth century”, Ph.D. dissertation, London School of Economics, London.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl (1976), Unended Quest. An Intellectual Autobiography. Revised Edition. Glasgow: Collins.Google Scholar
Weintraub, E. Roy (forthcoming), General Equilibrium Analysis: Studies in Appraisal. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. manuscript.Google Scholar