Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dsjbd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T04:42:14.070Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Mental Models in Data Interpretation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Clark A. Chinn
Affiliation:
Rutgers University
William F. Brewer
Affiliation:
University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign

Abstract

This paper presents a cognitive account of the process of evaluating scientific data. Our account assumes that when individuals evaluate data, they construct a mental model of a data-interpretation package, in which the data and theoretical interpretations of the data are integrated. We propose that individuals attempt to discount data by seeking alternative explanations for events within the mental model; data-interpretation packages are accepted when the individual cannot find alternative accounts for these events. Our analysis indicates that there are many levels at which data-interpretation packages can be accepted or denied.

Type
Philosophical Issues in Cognitive Science
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1996

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Department of Psychology, Rutgers University, New Brunswick, NJ.

Department of Psychology, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, 603 East Daniel St., Champaign, IL 61820.

References

Bogen, J. and Woodward, J. (1988), “Saving the Phenomena”, Philosophical Review 95: 303352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brewer, W. F. and Chinn, C. A. (1994), “Scientists' Responses to Anomalous Data: Evidence from Psychology, History, and Philosophy of Science”, in Hull, D., Forbes, M. and Burian, R. M. (eds.), PSA 1994, vol. 1. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 304313.Google Scholar
Gentner, D. and Stevens, A. L. (eds.), (1983), Mental Models. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Giere, R. N. (1985), “Philosophy of Science Naturalized”, Philosophy of Science 52: 331356.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanson, N. R. (1958), Patterns of Discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1983), Mental Models. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kunda, Z. (1990), “The Case for Motivated Reasoning”, Psychological Bulletin 108: 480498.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Peirce, C. S. (1931), Collected Papers, vol. 1. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Raup, D. M. (1986), The Nemesis Affair: A Story of the Death of Dinosaurs and the Ways of Science. New York: W. W. Norton.Google Scholar
Solomon, M. (1992), “Scientific Rationality and Human Reasoning”, Philosophy of Science 59: 439455.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suppe, F. (1974), “The Search for Philosophic Understanding of Scientific Theories”, in Suppe, F. (ed.), The Structure of Scientific Theories. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press, pp. 3241.Google Scholar
Suppes, P. (1962), “Models of Data”, in Nagel, E., Suppes, P. and Tarski, A. (eds.), Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science: Proceedings of the 1960 International Congress. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, pp. 252261.Google Scholar
Woodward, J. (1989), “Data and Phenomena”, Synthese 79: 393472.CrossRefGoogle Scholar