Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rcrh6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-21T22:28:15.990Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Invisible Hands and the Success of Science

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

K. Brad Wray*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of British Columbia

Abstract

David Hull accounts for the success of science in terms of an invisible hand mechanism, arguing that it is difficult to reconcile scientists' self-interestedness or their desire for recognition with traditional philosophical explanations for the success of science. I argue that we have less reason to invoke an invisible hand mechanism to explain the success of science than Hull implies, and that many of the practices and institutions constitutive of science are intentionally designed by scientists with an eye to realizing the very goals that Hull believes need to be explained by reference to an invisible hand mechanism. Thus, I reduce the scope of Hull's invisible hand explanation and supplement it by appealing to a hidden hand explanation.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 2000 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Send requests for reprints to the author, Department of Philosophy, University of British Columbia, 1866 Main Mall, E-370, Vancouver, British Columbia, V6T 1Z1.

David Hull's detailed and probing comments on an earlier draft helped me improve the paper substantially. Lori Nash read numerous drafts and provided much helpful feedback. I also received helpful comments from the following people: Marc Ereshefsky, Tracy Glenn, Mark Migotti, Bob Ware, Jay Odenbaugh, and Francis Remedios. Eugene Beaulieu provided valuable information about the uses of invisible hand explanations in economics. I also thank the referees for their reports. Finally, I thank the Canadian Society for History and Philosophy of Science for the opportunity to present the paper at the annual meetings in Sherbrooke, in June 1999, and the 11th International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science for the opportunity to present the paper at their meetings in Cracow, in August 1999.

References

Barnes, Barry, Bloor, D., and Henry, J. (1996), Scientific Knowledge: A Sociological Analysis. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Bechtel, William (1991), “Review of David Hull, Science as a Process”, Philosophy of Science 58: 138139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cole, Stephen (1992), Making Science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin (1995), “Social Epistemology, Interests, and Truth,” Philosophical Topics 23: 171187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, Alvin. (1999), Knowledge in a Social World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hands, D. Wade (1995), “Social Epistemology Meets the Invisible Hand: Kitcher on the Advancement of Science”, Dialogue XXXIV: 605621.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hands, D. Wade. (1997), “Caveat Emptor: Economics and Contemporary Philosophy of Science”, Philosophy of Science 64 (Proceedings): S107S116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harding, Sandra (1991), Whose Science? Whose Knowledge? Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Hardwig, John (1985), “Epistemic Dependence”, The Journal of Philosophy 82: 335349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, David (1988), Science as a Process. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, David. (1989), “Altruism in Science: A Sociobiological Model of Cooperative Behavior Among Scientists”, in The Metaphysics of Evolution. Albany: SUNY Press, 243262.Google Scholar
Hull, David. (1997), “What's Wrong With Invisible-Hand Explanations?”, Philosophy of Science 64 (Proceedings): S117S126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keller, Evelyn F. and Longino, H. (eds.) (1996), Feminism and Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google ScholarPubMed
Kitcher, Philip (1993), The Advancement of Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kyburg, Henry (1993), “Review of David Hull, Science as Process”, Noûs XXVII: 107109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Latour, Bruno and Woolgar, S. (1986), Laboratory Life, 2nd ed. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Longino, Helen (1990), Science as Social Knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Merton, Robert (1973a), “Priorities in Scientific Discovery”, in The Sociology of Science: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 286324.Google Scholar
Merton, Robert. (1973b), “Singletons and Multiple Discoveries in Science”, in The Sociology of Science: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 343370.Google Scholar
Merton, Robert. (1973c), “Institutionalized Patterns of Evaluation in Science”, in The Sociology of Science: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 460496.Google Scholar
Merton, Robert. (1973d), “Behavior Patterns of Scientists”, in The Sociology of Science: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 325342.Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert (1974), Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Rawling, Alison (1994), “The AIDS Virus Dispute: Awarding Priority for the Discovery of the Human Immunodeficiency Virus (HIV)”, Science, Technology, and Human Values 19: 342360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rorty, Richard (1991), “Is Natural Science a Natural Kind?”, in Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 4662.Google Scholar
Shapin, Steven (1996), The Scientific Revolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Adam ([1776]1970), The Wealth of Nations. London: J. M. Dent and Sons.Google Scholar
Solomon, Miriam (1992), “Scientific Rationality and Human Reasoning”, Philosophy of Science 59: 439455.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solomon, Miriam. (1994a), “Social Empiricism”, Noûs 28: 325343.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solomon, Miriam. (1994b), “Is There an Invisible Hand of Reason?”, unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
Sprat, Thomas ([1667]1959), History of the Royal Society. Cope, J. and Jones, H.W. (eds.). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Ullmann-Margalit, Edna (1978), “Invisible-Hand Explanations”, Synthese 39: 263291.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wray, K. Brad (1999), “A Defense of Longino's Social Epistemology”, Philosophy of Science 66 (Proceedings): S538S552.Google Scholar
Ylikoski, Petri (1995), “The Invisible Hand and Science”, Science Studies 8: 3243.Google Scholar