Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-fbnjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T10:26:32.427Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Hypothetical Pattern Idealization and Explanatory Models

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

Highly idealized models, such as the Hawk-Dove game, are pervasive in biological theorizing. We argue that the process and motivation that leads to the introduction of various idealizations into these models is not adequately captured by Michael Weisberg’s taxonomy of three kinds of idealization. Consequently, a fourth kind of idealization is required, which we call hypothetical pattern idealization. This kind of idealization is used to construct models that aim to be explanatory but do not aim to be explanations.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Both authors contributed equally to this work. We would like to thank Chris Pincock, André Ariew, Paul Weirich, Michael Weisberg, William Wimsatt, and several anonymous reviewers for comments and feedback on previous versions of this article. We would also like to thank the members of the University of Pittsburgh’s Center for the Philosophy of Science for helpful discussion, comments, and support. This research was partially supported by the Al and Mary Agnes McQuinn Chair in Entrepreneurial Leadership.

References

Achinstein, Peter. 1983. The Nature of Explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Batterman, Robert W. 2002. The Devil in the Details: Asymptotic Reasoning in Explanation, Reduction, and Emergence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bokulich, Alisa. 2012. “Distinguishing Explanatory and Nonexplanatory Fictions.” Philosophy of Science 79:725–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy. 1983. How the Laws of Physics Lie. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy 1989. Nature’s Capacities and Their Measurement. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Depaul, Michael, and Grimm, Stephen. 2007. Review of The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding, by Jonathan Kvanvig. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74:498514.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forber, Patrick. 2010. “Confirmation and Explaining How Possible.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 41:3240.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Friedman, Michael. 1974. “Explanation and Scientific Understanding.” Journal of Philosophy 71:519.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, Peter. 2006. “The Strategy of Model-Based Science.” Biology and Philosophy 21:725–40.Google Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, Peter 2009. “Models and Fictions in Science.” Philosophical Studies 143:101–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grimm, Stephen. 2006. “Is Understanding a Species of Knowledge?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57:515–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grüne-Yanoff, Till. 2009. “Learning from Minimal Economic Models.” Erkenntnis 70:8199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, Carl G. 1965. Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip. 1981. “Explanatory Unification.” Philosophy of Science 48:507–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knuuttila, Tarja. 2009. “Isolation Representations versus Credible Constructions? Economic Modeling in Theory and Practice.” Erkenntnis 70:5980.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kvanvig, Jonathan. 2003. The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levins, Richard. 1966. “The Strategy of Model Building in Population Biology.” American Scientist 54:421–31.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 1986. Philosophical Papers. Pt. 2. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lipton, Peter. 2009. “Understanding without Explanation.” In Scientific Understanding: Philosophical Perspectives, ed. de Regt, Henk W., Leonelli, Sabina, and Eigner, Kai, 4363. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maynard Smith, John. 1982. Evolution and the Theory of Games. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maynard Smith, John, and Parker, Geoffery A.. 1976. “The Logic of Asymmetric Contests.” Animal Behavior 24:159–75.Google Scholar
Maynard Smith, John, and Price, G. R.. 1973. “The Logic of Animal Conflict.” Nature 246:1518.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMullin, Ernan. 1985. “Galilean Idealization.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 16:247–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mizrahi, Moti. 2012. “Idealizations and Scientific Understanding.” Philosophical Studies 160:237–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morgan, M. S. 1999. “Learning from Models.” In Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science, ed. Morgan, M. and Morrison, M., 347–88. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nowak, Leszek. 1972. “Laws of Science, Theories, Measurement.” Philosophy of Science 39 (4): 533–48..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pincock, Christopher. 2012. “Mathematical Models of Biological Patterns: Lessons from Hamilton’s Selfish Herd.” Biology and Philosophy 27:481–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Potochnik, Angela. 2007. “Optimality Modeling and Explanatory Generality.” Philosophy of Science 74:680–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Resnik, David B. 1991. “How-Possibly Explanations in Biology.” Acta Biotheoretica 39:141–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reydon, Thomas A. C. 2012. “How-Possibly Explanations as Genuine Explanations and Helpful Heuristics: A Comment on Forber.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 43:302–10.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rice, Collin. 2012. “Optimality Explanations: A Plea for an Alternative Approach.” Biology and Philosophy 27 (5): 685703..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rohwer, Yasha. Forthcoming. “Lucky Understanding without Knowledge.” Synthese.Google Scholar
Salmon, Wesley. 1998. Causality and Explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schelling, Thomas. 1978. Micromotives and Macrobehavior. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott. 1983. “Equilibrium Explanation.” Philosophical Studies 43:201–10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, Elliott 2000. Philosophy of Biology. 2nd ed. Boulder, CO: Westview.Google Scholar
Strevens, Michael. 2009. Depth: An Account of Scientific Explanation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Suárez, Mauricio. 1999. “The Role of Models in the Application of Scientific Theories: Epistemological Implications.” In Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science, ed. Morgan, M. and Morrison, M., 168–96. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Morrison, M. 2009. Fictions in Science: Philosophical Essays on Modeling and Idealization. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Sugden, R. 2000. “Credible Worlds: The Status of Theoretical Models in Economics.” Journal of Economic Methodology 7:131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, R. 2009. “Credible Worlds, Capacities and Mechanisms.” Erkenntnis 670:327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas C. 1980. The Scientific Image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wayne, Andrew. 2011. “Expanding the Scope of Explanatory Idealization.” Philosophy of Science 78:830–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weisberg, Michael. 2007. “Three Kinds of Idealization.” Journal of Philosophy 104:639–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wimsatt, William. 2007. Re-engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings: Piecewise Approximations of Reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodward, James. 2003. Making Things Happen: A Theory of Causal Explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar