Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-4rdpn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T22:18:55.680Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Exploring an Evolutionary Paradox: An Analysis of the “Spite Effect” and the “Nearly Neutral Effect” in Synergistic Models of Finite Populations

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 February 2023

Emily Heydon*
Affiliation:
University of California Irvine, Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science, Irvine, CA, USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Forber and Smead (2014) analyze how increasing the fitness benefits associated with prosocial behavior can increase the fitness of spiteful individuals relative to their prosocial counterparts, so that selection favors spite over prosociality. This poses a problem for the evolution of prosocial behavior: As the benefits of prosocial behavior increase, it becomes more likely that spite, not prosocial behavior, will evolve in any given population. In this article, I develop two game-theoretic models that, taken together, illustrate how synergistic costs and benefits may provide partial solutions to Forber and Smead’s paradox.

Type
Contributed Paper
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Philosophy of Science Association

1. Introduction

While the evolution of prosocial behavior has been heavily studied, far less attention has been given to the evolution of spite. Spite, which has been referred to as “the dark side of cooperation,” can evolve when selfish individuals “exploit the system.” Spiteful individuals benefit from interacting with prosocial individuals but pay a personal fitness cost to withhold benefits from those they interact with (Jensen Reference Jensen2010). This definition of spite requires that a spiteful individual incur some cost from its own spiteful behavior. However, it is still possible for spite to be advantageous, if the benefits accrued from interacting with prosocial individuals outweigh this cost.

Correlated interactions are a key factor in the evolution of prosocial behavior; if prosocial individuals can recognize, and preferentially interact with, other prosocial individuals, there will be correlated interactions between individuals playing the same behavior strategies. In other words, prosocial individuals will be more likely to interact with other prosocial individuals, while spiteful individuals will be more likely to interact with other spiteful individuals. Such correlations between behavior strategies ensure that the benefits of prosocial behavior are, to the extent possible, bestowed only upon prosocial individuals who are willing to reciprocate others’ generosity (Smead and Forber Reference Smead and Forber2012; Skyrms Reference Skyrms1996).

Similarly, anticorrelated interactions are necessary for the evolution of spite. In other words, spite can only evolve when a spiteful individual is more likely to interact with a prosocial individual, and vice versa. In finite populations, a slight degree of anticorrelation is always present, and this is because each individual is unable to interact with itself; this effect may be likened to “sampling without replacement.” This anticorrelation opens the door to the evolution of spite, leaving populations of prosocial individuals vulnerable to invasion by spiteful individuals (Forber and Smead Reference Forber and Smead2014; Birch Reference Birch2017).

To summarize, if (1) the cost of performing a spiteful behavior is relatively small, compared to the benefit gained by exploiting prosocial individuals; and (2) there is sufficient anticorrelation among behavior strategies; then (3) it is possible for the fitness of spiteful individuals to exceed the fitness of prosocial individuals, meaning that selection favors spite. Because finite populations always entail some degree of anticorrelation, it is possible for spite to evolve in a finite population if the benefits exceed the costs.

2. An Evolutionary Paradox

In their 2014 paper, “An Evolutionary Paradox for Prosocial Behavior,” Forber and Smead analyze how increasing the benefits of prosocial behavior impacts the fitness of spiteful individuals, relative to the fitness of prosocial individuals. Assuming pairwise interactions in a finite population, Forber and Smead model a game-theoretic scenario similar to the one described in the previous section. However, rather than analyzing a prisoner’s dilemma–style game, Forber and Smead propose a scenario in which mutual prosocial behavior should, theoretically, be less difficult to achieve. In such a game, sometimes referred to as a prisoner’s delight, the greatest payoffs are earned when both individuals play the prosocial strategyFootnote 1 (Binmore Reference Binmore2007; Skyrms Reference Skyrms2007).

In Forber and Smead’s model, individuals are assumed to be one of two types—either prosocial or spiteful—and it is assumed that both behavior strategies are played unconditionally. In this model, interacting with a prosocial individual confers a benefit on the recipient, but prosocial individuals cannot benefit from their own prosocial behavior. Spiteful individuals benefit from interacting with prosocial individuals, while incurring a cost due to their own spiteful behavior. Due to the inherent costs associated with spite, one might expect selection to always favor prosocial behavior. However, Forber and Smead’s analysis reveals a paradoxical result: Increasing the benefit of prosocial behavior can increase the fitness of spiteful individuals, so that selection favors spite over prosociality.

Forber and Smead describe two effects that drive this relative increase in the fitness of spiteful individuals. The first is the “spite effect,” or the tendency of spiteful individuals in a finite population to reap disproportionate rewards from others’ prosocial behavior, due to anticorrelated interactions. Because prosocial individuals are more likely to interact with spiteful individuals than they are to interact with other prosocial individuals, spiteful individuals are more likely (than their prosocial counterparts) to receive the fitness benefits of prosocial behavior. The second is the “nearly neutral effect,” or the tendency for spiteful behavior to evolve by chance when the benefits of prosocial behavior are large and the fitness difference between the two behavior strategies is small. In such a situation, selection is “nearly neutral” with respect to behavior strategies, and the question of which strategy evolves in a given population is largely dependent on drift. As I will explore later in this article, it is possible to isolate the nearly neutral effect (or, in other words, to remove the spite effect) by removing the anticorrelations from the fitness functionsFootnote 2 (Forber and Smead Reference Forber and Smead2014).

In this article, I will analyze both the spite effect and the nearly neutral effect by considering two other game-theoretic scenarios. Both scenarios share many characteristics with the model developed by Forber and Smead (Reference Forber and Smead2014), while including additional variables to describe the effects of synergism. First, I will analyze a synergistic-cost model, in which spiteful individuals incur an additional cost whenever they interact with each other.Footnote 3 Then, I will analyze a synergistic-benefit model, in which mutual prosocial behavior earns an additional benefit.Footnote 4 I will show that each of these synergistic models provides a partial solution to Forber and Smead’s paradox, by increasing the fitness of prosocial individuals relative to their spiteful counterparts.

A article by Ventura (Reference Ventura2019) likewise analyzed how the addition of synergistic effects to Forber and Smead’s model can provide a partial solution to the evolutionary paradox. However, Ventura’s definition of synergism differs from mine, with the result that our analyses and proposed solutions to the paradox are quite different. In Ventura’s model, the benefit of prosocial behavior is synergistic in the sense that it is a nonlinear function of the number of prosocial individuals, with the benefit decreasing as the number of prosocial individuals approaches the total population size. In my analysis, the benefit of prosocial behavior and the cost of spiteful behavior are not dependent on the number of either type of individual in the population. Rather, in my models, the cost of spiteful behavior is synergistic in the sense that a spiteful individual incurs an additional cost whenever it plays its spiteful strategy against another spiteful individual. Similarly, the benefit of prosocial behavior is synergistic in the sense that a prosocial individual reaps an additional benefit when interacting with another prosocial individual. The overall result is that mutual prosocial behavior is incentivized, mutual spiteful behavior is disincentivized, and the paradoxical effects noted by Forber and Smead (Reference Forber and Smead2014) are dampened to an extent.

3. A Game-Theoretic Model for the Evolution of Spiteful Behavior in Finite Populations

Forber and Smead (Reference Forber and Smead2014) investigate the evolution of spite in finite populations. As discussed in the previous section, they assume a game-theoretic scenario referred to as a prisoner’s delight, in which the greatest net benefits are gained through mutual prosocial behavior. Their analysis assumes pairwise interactions, with the payoffs shown in Table 1.

Table 1. b > a > 0

Prosocial Spiteful
Prosocial b 1
Spiteful ba 1 – a

Individuals are assumed to be one of two types: prosocial or spiteful. Payoffs are given for the player on the left-hand side. Prosocial behavior confers a benefit b on the recipient, while spite is defined as the withholding of this benefit b, at a cost a to oneself. If two prosocial individuals interact, then both individuals receive the benefit b. If two spiteful individuals interact, they both receive the baseline fitness (1), minus the cost, a, of their own spiteful behavior. If two individuals of different types interact, the prosocial individual receives the baseline fitness (1), while the spiteful individual receives the benefit b (from interacting with a prosocial individual) minus the cost, a, of its own spiteful behavior.

Using the payoffs given in Table 1, Forber and Smead (Reference Forber and Smead2014) calculate the fitness functions of both types:

(1) $$F\left( {p,\;N} \right) = {{b\left( {{x_p} - 1} \right) + {x_s}} \over {N - 1}}$$
(2) $$F\left( {s,\;N} \right) = {{(b - a){x_p} + \left( {1 - a} \right)\left( {{x_s} - 1} \right)} \over {N - 1}}$$

Table 2. b > a > 0, c > 0

Prosocial Spiteful
Prosocial b 1
Spiteful ba 1 – ac

N represents the finite population size, while the numbers of prosocial and spiteful individuals are represented by x p and x s , respectively. Prosocial behavior is favored when F(p,N) > F(s,N), while spite is favored when F(p,N) < F(s,N). As discussed in the previous section, when the fitnesses of the two types are approximately equal, selection is relatively neutral with respect to behavior strategies, and drift plays the more significant evolutionary role (Forber and Smead Reference Forber and Smead2014). Because all interactions occur within a finite population, there is a small degree of anticorrelation between behavior strategies. As discussed in the preceding text, this anticorrelation opens the door to the evolution of spite, by enabling spiteful individuals to benefit disproportionately from others’ prosocial behavior. As Forber and Smead’s analysis shows, increasing the benefit (b) of prosocial behavior can increase the fitness of spiteful individuals, relative to the fitness of prosocial individuals, so that F(p,N) < F(s,N). Substituting the fitness functions into the two inequalities given in the preceding text, we see that prosociality is favored in this model when b < a(N – 1) + 1, while spite is favored when b > a(N – 1) + 1. Forber and Smead (Reference Forber and Smead2014) conduct simulations to show that, as the benefit (b) increases, spiteful behavior evolves in an increasingly large proportion of populations, and the effect is strongest for small (e.g., N = 25) population sizes.

In the final portion of their article, Forber and Smead (Reference Forber and Smead2014) remove the anticorrelations from the fitness functions to analyze the nearly neutral effect in isolation. That is to say, they remove the spite effect from the simulations by getting rid of the slight degree of anticorrelation that results from the finite population size. To facilitate this analysis, Forber and Smead first introduce the concept of a selection coefficient, which is a commonly used method for comparing the fitnesses of two traits.Footnote 5 Using s c to represent the selection coefficient, and the fitness of prosocial individuals as baseline, the relative fitnesses of the two behavior strategies are as follows:

(3) $${F_r}\left( {p,N} \right) = 1$$
(4) $${F_r}\left( {s,N} \right) = \;{{F\left( {s,N} \right)} \over {F\left( {p,N} \right)}} = 1 - {s_c}$$

The symbol F r is used to denote relative fitness. Substituting equations (1) and (2) for the fitnesses of the two types, Forber and Smead rearrange equation (4) to yield the following:

(5) $${s_c} = {{a\left( {N - 1} \right) - b + 1} \over {b\left( {{x_p} - 1} \right) + {x_s}}}$$

Observe what happens when the benefit (b) of prosocial behavior is increased. Because b is subtracted from the numerator of equation (5), but is a product in the denominator, increasing b decreases the selection coefficient. Decreasing the selection coefficient brings the ratio of the fitnesses [F(s,N)/F(p,N)] close to one, meaning that there is only a slight fitness difference between the two behavior strategies. As discussed in the preceding text, when the fitness difference between the two strategies is small, selection is effectively neutral, and the direction of evolution in any given population is governed primarily by drift (Forber and Smead, Reference Forber and Smead2014).

Forber and Smead next apply this concept of a “nearly neutral model” to their original analysis to observe how increasing the benefit (b) of prosocial behavior can cause the evolutionary dynamics to become more neutral in character (Forber and Smead, Reference Forber and Smead2014). To do this, they isolate the nearly neutral effect by removing the anticorrelations from the original fitness functions. The revised fitness functions are then as follows:

(6) $$F\left( {p,\;N} \right) = {{b\left( {{x_p}} \right) + {x_s}} \over N}$$
(7) $$F\left( {s,\;N} \right) = {{(b\; - \;a){x_p} + \left( {1 - a} \right){x_s}} \over N}$$

Forber and Smead then repeat their simulations, using the revised fitness functions; the result is that, when the nearly neutral effect is isolated, spiteful behavior generally evolves less frequently for any given value of b. However, spite still becomes more and more likely to evolve in a given population as the benefits of prosocial behavior increase, with the likelihood approaching a limit of 0.5 as the fitness difference between the two strategies approaches zero. Plugging equations 6 and 7 into the inequality F(s,N) > F(p,N), we see that selection will never favor spite as long as the cost of spite is greater than zero (a > 0). Nevertheless, increasing the benefit (b) of prosocial behavior decreases the fitness difference between the two behavior types, making it more likely that spite will evolve in a given population due to drift alone.

4. The Synergistic-Cost Model

In the following analysis, I will consider two other game-theoretic scenarios. Both retain the general format used by Forber and Smead (Reference Forber and Smead2014), while introducing additional variables to describe synergistic effects. The first scenario involves a synergistic cost, c, which is incurred by two spiteful individuals whenever they interact with each other (Table 2).

The fitness functions for this scenario are as follows:

(1) $$F\left( {p,\;N} \right) = {{b\left( {{x_p} - 1} \right) + {x_s}} \over {N - 1}}$$
(8) $$F\left( {s,\;N} \right) = {{\left( {b - a} \right){x_p} + \left( {1 - a - c} \right)\left( {{x_s} - 1} \right)} \over {N - 1}}$$

Plugging these formulas into the inequality F(s,N) > F(p,N), we see that selection favors spite when b > ax p + a(x s – 1) + c(x s – 1) + 1. Similarly, selection favors prosocial behavior when b < ax p + a(x s – 1) + c(x s – 1) + 1. Consider a population size of N = 100, with a = 0.1 and c = 0.1 (Figure 1).Footnote 6 Observe that increasing the benefit (b) of prosocial behavior decreases the fitness of prosocial individuals; this is the paradox that Forber and Smead (Reference Forber and Smead2014) observed. At relatively low values of b, the selection coefficient remains above zero, meaning that the effect is not strong enough for selection to favor spite. However, as shown in Figure 1, at higher values of b (e.g., b = 26), the selection coefficient drops below zero, indicating that selection favors spite.

Figure 1. In all figures, a = 0.1 and N = 100. x p on x-axis; s c on y-axis.

Nevertheless, we see that the introduction of a synergistic cost provides a partial solution to the evolutionary paradox. If, as shown in Figure 2, we set c = 0, with N = 100 and a = 0.1, and increase the benefit (b) of prosocial behavior, the selection coefficient becomes negative at relatively low values of b (e.g., b = 14).Footnote 7 However, if we add a large synergistic cost by setting c = 1 (Figure 2), we see that the selection coefficient generally remains positive, unless the value of b is high (e.g., b = 26) and the number of prosocial individuals is large (e.g., x p = 80). Therefore, if mutual spiteful behavior incurs synergistic costs, it is easier for prosocial behavior to evolve, and more difficult for spite to gain an evolutionary foothold.

Figure 2. In all figures, a = 0.1 and N = 100. x p on x-axis; s c on y-axis.

5. The Synergistic-Benefit Model

Having analyzed a synergistic-cost model, let us now turn to a synergistic-benefit model. Suppose that, when two prosocial individuals interact, they mutually confer a synergistic benefit, d, on each other. The payoffs for this scenario are given in Table 3.

Table 3. b > a > 0, d > 0

Prosocial Spiteful
Prosocial b + d 1
Spiteful ba 1 – a

The fitness functions are now as follows:

(9) $$F\left( {p,\;N} \right) = \;{{\left( {b + d} \right)\left( {{x_p} - 1} \right) + \;{x_s}} \over {N - 1}}$$
(2) $$F\left( {s,\;N} \right) = {{\left( {b - a} \right){x_p} + \left( {1 - a} \right)\left( {{x_s} - 1} \right)} \over {N - 1}}$$

Now, we see that selection favors spite when b > d(x p – 1) + a(N – 1) + 1, and that selection favors prosociality when b < d(x p – 1) + a(N – 1) + 1. Once again, the evolutionary paradox emerges. As the benefit (b) of prosocial behavior increases, the selection coefficient becomes smaller and smaller, and selection can favor spite at very large values of b. Nevertheless, we see that the inclusion of a synergistic benefit, like the inclusion of a synergistic cost, has the potential to significantly diminish these paradoxical effects (Figure 3). When there is no synergistic benefit (d = 0), and we increase the value of b, the paradox is noticeably present. At larger values of b, the selection coefficient falls just below zero, giving spite a slight fitness advantage (Figure 3). However, in the presence of a large synergistic benefit (Figure 3, d = 1), the selection coefficient generally remains above zero at larger values of b (e.g., b = 26). Spite is generally selected against, especially if x p is large.

Figure 3. In all figures, a = 0.1 and N = 100. x p on x-axis; s c on y-axis.

Because only prosocial individuals receive synergistic benefits, the addition of a synergistic benefit generally gives prosocial individuals a fitness advantage over their spiteful counterparts. For the previously mentioned reasons we see that, like the synergistic-cost model, the synergistic-benefit model provides a partial solution to Forber and Smead’s paradox.

6. Isolating the Nearly Neutral Effect

Recall that, in their analysis, Forber and Smead (Reference Forber and Smead2014) isolate the nearly neutral effect by removing the anticorrelations from the fitness functions. The result is that, as the benefit (b) of prosocial behavior increases, the fitness difference between the two behavior strategies approaches zero, and selection behaves in a “nearly neutral” manner. That is to say, when the fitness difference between the prosocial and spiteful strategies is very small, selection does not strongly favor one strategy over the other, and the question of which strategy evolves in a given population is largely dependent on drift.

I have already demonstrated that when mutual prosocial behavior earns synergistic benefits, or when mutual spiteful behavior incurs synergistic costs, selection is less likely to favor spite over prosociality, even when the benefit of prosocial behavior is rather large. Next, I will show that when the nearly neutral effect is isolated selection cannot favor spite if mutual spiteful behavior incurs synergistic costs or mutual prosocial behavior earns synergistic benefits. Still, as we will see, the nearly neutral effect poses a problem for the evolution of prosocial behavior: even if mutual spite entails synergistic costs, or mutual prosociality earns synergistic benefits, the influence of drift becomes stronger as the benefit (b) of prosocial behavior increases. When the benefits of prosocial behavior are very large, and spiteful individuals cannot reap the additional fitness benefits associated with anticorrelated interactions between behavior strategies, Footnote 8 the direction of evolution depends primarily on drift—not selection—and so spite may still evolve in roughly half of all populations.

To observe this phenomenon, let us first isolate the nearly neutral effect in the synergistic-cost model. We remove the anticorrelations from the original fitness functions:

(6) $$F\left( {p,\;N} \right) = {{b\left( {{x_p}} \right) + {x_s}} \over N}$$
(10) $$F\left( {s,\;N} \right) = \;{{\left( {b - a} \right){x_p} + \left( {1 - a - c} \right){x_s}} \over N}$$

Spite is favored when c < –aN/x s and prosociality is favored when c > –aN/x s . In other words, if (1) the value of a is positive (meaning that spiteful individuals incur a cost from their own spiteful behavior, regardless of whom they interact with) and (2) mutual spiteful behavior incurs positive synergistic costs, selection will always favor prosociality and never favor spite. This result is shown in Figure 4; when c = 1, the selection coefficient remains positive, but when c = –1, selection generally favors spite.

Figure 4. In all figures, a = 0.1 and N = 100. x p on x-axis; s c on y-axis.

Next, consider the synergistic-benefit model. Again, we isolate the nearly neutral effect by removing the anticorrelations from the original fitness functions:

(11) $$F\left( {p,\;N} \right) = \;{{\left( {b + d} \right){x_p} + {x_s}} \over N}$$
(7) $$F\left( {s,\;N} \right) = {{(b\; - \;a){x_p} + \left( {1 - a} \right){x_s}} \over N}$$

Spite is favored when d < –aN/x p and prosociality is favored when d > –aN/x p . In other words, if (1) the value of a is positive and (2) mutual prosocial behavior earns positive synergistic benefits, selection will always favor prosocial behavior and will never favor spite. This result is shown in Figure 5. When d = 1, the selection coefficient remains positive, but when d = –1, selection generally favors spite unless x p is small.

Figure 5. In all figures, a = 0.1 and N = 100. x p on x-axis; s c on y-axis.

However, as the benefit (b) of prosocial behavior increases in both models, the selection coefficient approaches zero. That is to say, as the benefit of prosocial behavior increases, the fitness difference between the two behavior strategies approaches zero, and at very high values of b, the question of which behavior strategy evolves in a given population is largely dependent on drift, not selection. It is true that, when the nearly neutral effect is isolated, selection cannot favor spite if mutual spite entails synergistic costs or mutual prosocial behavior earns synergistic benefits. Nevertheless, as the benefit of prosocial behavior increases in either model, it becomes more and more likely that spite will evolve through the effects of drift alone.

7. Discussion

Forber and Smead (Reference Forber and Smead2014) present a paradox for the evolution of prosocial behavior: As the benefits associated with prosocial behavior are increased, the fitness of spiteful individuals also increases. If the fitness of spiteful individuals exceeds the fitness of prosocial individuals, then selection will favor spite. That is to say, increasing the benefits of prosocial behavior may decrease the likelihood that prosocial behavior will evolve in a given population. The paradox is salient in models of finite populations, where a slight anticorrelation of behavior strategies typically enables spiteful individuals to reap disproportionate benefits from others’ prosocial behavior.

Forber and Smead divide the paradox into two distinct effects: the “spite effect,” which they define as the fitness advantage enjoyed by spiteful individuals due to the anticorrelation of interactions in a finite population, and the “nearly neutral effect,” or the tendency for spiteful behavior to evolve through drift, when the benefits of prosocial behavior are large and the fitness difference between the two behavior strategies is small. Forber and Smead’s analysis shows that, when the nearly neutral effect is isolated—that is to say, when spiteful individuals are prevented from reaping additional fitness benefits associated with anticorrelated interactions between behavior strategies—it becomes relatively more difficult for spite to evolve, even when the benefits of prosocial behavior are rather large. However, even when the nearly neutral effect is isolated, the paradox still poses a problem for the evolution of prosocial behavior: As the benefits associated with prosocial behavior increase, it becomes more and more likely that spite will evolve through the effects of drift alone.

In an attempt to provide a solution to this problem, in this article I have developed two game-theoretic models, both involving pairwise interactions in a finite population. Both are similar to the model used by Forber and Smead (Reference Forber and Smead2014), but include additional variables to describe synergistic effects. The first involves a synergistic cost, incurred whenever two spiteful individuals interact with each other, and the second involves a synergistic benefit, earned through mutual prosocial behavior. Each model provides a partial solution to the paradox, by increasing the fitness of prosocial individuals relative to their spiteful counterparts; the result is that, when mutual spite incurs synergistic costs, or when mutual prosocial behavior earns synergistic benefits, it becomes more likely that selection will favor prosociality over spite, even when the benefits of prosocial behavior are relatively large.

Nevertheless, isolating the nearly neutral effect reveals that as the benefits of prosocial behavior increase, the fitness difference between the two behavior strategies approaches zero, and it becomes more likely that spite—not prosocial behavior—will evolve in any given population, simply due to drift. So, although synergistic costs and benefits can provide prosocial individuals with a fitness advantage over their spiteful counterparts, Forber and Smead’s paradox remains, albeit in a weaker form. As the benefits of prosocial behavior increase, it becomes more likely that drift will lead spite to evolve in any given population.

Acknowledgments

Many thanks to Hannah Rubin, Simon Huttegger, Rory Smead, and Brian Skyrms for helpful comments that influenced the development of the paper.

Competing interests

The author declares none.

Footnotes

1 Payoff table given in section 3.

2 Fitness functions given in next section.

3 Mutual spite may incur synergistic costs. For example, imagine that spiteful individuals quarrel/fight whenever they interact with each other. Each individual incurs a cost due to its own spiteful behavior (the “inherent” cost of spite), and additionally incurs synergistic costs (e.g., bodily injury, time, and energy spent fighting).

4 There are several ways in which mutual prosocial behavior may involve synergistic benefits. An example is cooperative hunting, in which prosocial individuals may be able to kill more/larger prey by working in pairs/groups, resulting in more food (benefits) for all the individuals involved.

5 Prosocial behavior is favored when the selection coefficient is greater than zero, and spiteful behavior is favored when the selection coefficient is less than zero.

6 A value of a = 0.1 was also used by Forber and Smead (Reference Forber and Smead2014).

7 When c = 0, there is no synergistic cost.

8 This condition may be met if prosocial individuals can, with a sufficient degree of accuracy, identify spiteful individuals and avoid interacting with them.

References

Binmore, Kenneth. 2007. Game Theory: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/actrade/9780199218462.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Birch, Jonathan. 2017. The Philosophy of Social Evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Forber, Patrick, and Smead, Rory. 2014. “An Evolutionary Paradox for Prosocial Behavior.” The Journal of Philosophy 111 (3):151–66.Google Scholar
Jensen, Keith. 2010. “Punishment and Spite, the Dark Side of Cooperation.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 365 (1553):2635–50.Google Scholar
Skyrms, Brian. 1996. Evolution of the Social Contract. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Skyrms, Brian. 2007. “Evolution and the Social Contract.” The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, Department of Philosophy, University of Michigan.Google Scholar
Smead, Rory, and Forber, Patrick. 2012. “The Evolutionary Dynamics of Spite in Finite Populations.” Evolution 67 (3):698707.10.1111/j.1558-5646.2012.01831.xCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ventura, Rafael. 2019. “The Evolution of Cooperation in Finite Populations with Synergistic Payoffs.” Biology and Philosophy 34 (4):43.10.1007/s10539-019-9695-xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1. b > a > 0

Figure 1

Table 2. b > a > 0, c > 0

Figure 2

Figure 1. In all figures, a = 0.1 and N = 100. xp on x-axis; sc on y-axis.

Figure 3

Figure 2. In all figures, a = 0.1 and N = 100. xp on x-axis; sc on y-axis.

Figure 4

Table 3. b > a > 0, d > 0

Figure 5

Figure 3. In all figures, a = 0.1 and N = 100. xp on x-axis; sc on y-axis.

Figure 6

Figure 4. In all figures, a = 0.1 and N = 100. xp on x-axis; sc on y-axis.

Figure 7

Figure 5. In all figures, a = 0.1 and N = 100. xp on x-axis; sc on y-axis.