Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T00:35:25.387Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Explanatory Unification

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Philip Kitcher*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy University of Vermont

Abstract

The official model of explanation proposed by the logical empiricists, the covering law model, is subject to familiar objections. The goal of the present paper is to explore an unofficial view of explanation which logical empiricists have sometimes suggested, the view of explanation as unification. I try to show that this view can be developed so as to provide insight into major episodes in the history of science, and that it can overcome some of the most serious difficulties besetting the covering law model.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1981 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

A distant ancestor of this paper was read to the Dartmouth College Philosophy Colloquium in the Spring of 1977. I would like to thank those who participated, especially Merrie Bergmann and Jim Moor, for their helpful suggestions. I am also grateful to two anonymous referees for Philosophy of Science whose extremely constructive criticisms have led to substantial improvements. Finally, I want to acknowledge the amount I have learned from the writing and the teaching of Peter Hempel. The present essay is a token payment on an enormous debt.

References

REFERENCES

Achinstein, P. (1971), Law and Explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Achinstein, P. (1977), “What is an Explanation?”, American Philosophical Quarterly 14: pp. 115.Google Scholar
Belnap, N. and Steel, T. B. (1976), The Logic of Questions and Answers. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Boscovich, R. J. (1966), A Theory of Natural Philosophy (trans. J. M. Child). Cambridge: M.I.T. Press.Google Scholar
Bromberger, S. (1962), “An Approach to Explanation”, in Butler, R. J. (ed.), Analytical Philosophy (First Series). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Bromberger, S. (1966), “Why-Questions”, in Colodny, R. (ed.), Mind and Cosmos. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, I. B. (1956), Franklin and Newton. Philadelphia: American Philosophical Society.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. (1964), On the Origin of Species, Facsimile of the First Edition, edited by Mayr, E. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwin, F. (1887), The Life and Letters of Charles Darwin. London: John Murray.Google Scholar
Eberle, R., Kaplan, D., and Montague, R. (1961), “Hempel and Oppenheim on Explanation”, Philosophy of Science 28: pp. 418–28.Google Scholar
Feigl, H. (1970), “The ‘Orthodox’ View of Theories: Remarks in Defense as well as Critique”, in Radner, M. and Winokur, S. (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume IV. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Friedman, M. (1974), “Explanation and Scientific Understanding”, Journal of Philosophy LXXI: pp. 519.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heimann, P., and McGuire, J. E. (1971), “Newtonian Forces and Lockean Powers”, Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences 3: pp. 233306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, C. G. (1965), Aspects of Scientific Explanation. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. G. (1962), “Deductive-Nonlogical vs. Statistical Explanation”, in Feigl, H. and Maxwell, G. (eds.) Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume III. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. G. (1966), Philosophy of Natural Science. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Hull, D. (ed.) (1974), Darwin and his Critics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, R. (1970), “Statistical Explanation vs. Statistical Inference”, in Rescher, N. (ed.), Essays in Honor of Carl G. Hempel. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. S. (1976), “Explanation, Conjunction and Unification”, Journal of Philosophy, LXXIII: pp. 207–12.Google Scholar
Lavoisier, A. (1862), Oeuvres. Paris.Google Scholar
Newton, I. (1962), The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy (trans. A. Motte and F. Cajori). Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Newton, I. (1952), Opticks. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
Railton, P. (1978), “A Deductive-Nomological Model of Probabilistic Explanation”, Philosophy of Science 45: pp. 206226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, W. (1970), “Statistical Explanation”, in Colodny, R. (ed.), The Nature and Function of Scientific Theories. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
Schofield, R. E. (1969), Mechanism and Materialism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Teller, P. (1974), “On Why-Questions”, NoÛs VIII: pp. 371–80.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1977), “The Pragmatics of Explanation”, American Philosophical Quarterly 14: pp. 143–50.Google Scholar
Whyte, L. L. (ed.) (1961), Roger Joseph Boscovich. London: Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar